ANSELM'S PHILOSOPHY.
(AFTER WEBER.1)
"The first really speculative thinker after Scotus is St. Anselmus, the disciple
of Lanfranc. He was born at Aosta (1033),
iv |
"The second Augustine, as St. Anselmus had been called, starts out from the same principle as the first; he holds that faith precedes all reflection and all discussion concerning religious things. The unbelievers, he says, strive to understand because they do not believe; we, on the contrary, strive to understand because we believe. They and we have the same object in view; but inasmuch as they do not believe, they cannot arrive at their goal, which is to understand the dogma. The unbeliever will never understand. In religion faith plays the part played by experience in the understanding of the things of this world. The blind man cannot see the light, and therefore does not understand it; the deaf-mute, who has never perceived sound, cannot have a clear idea of sound. Similarly, not to believe means not to perceive, and not to perceive means not to understand. Hence, we do not reflect in order that we may believe; on the contrary, we believe in order that we may arrive at knowledge. A Christian ought never to doubt the beliefs and teachings of the Holy Catholic Church. All he can do is to strive, as humbly as possible, to understand her teachings by believing them, to love them, and resolutely to observe them in his daily life. Should he succeed in understanding the Christian doctrine, let him render thanks to God, the source of all intelligence! In case he fails, that is no reason why he should obstinately attack the dogma, but a reason why he should bow his head in worship. Faith ought not merely to be the starting-point, --the Christian's aim is not to depart from faith but to remain in it, --but also the fixed rule and goal of thought, the beginning, the middle, and the end of all philosophy.
"The above almost literal quotations might give one the
impression that St. Anselmus belongs exclusively to the
history of theology. Such is not the case, however. This fervent Catholic is
more independent, more of an investigator and philosopher than he himself
imagines. He is a typical scholastic doctor and a fine exponent of the alliance
between reason and faith which forms the characteristic trait of mediaeval
philosophy. He assumes,
v |
"Everything that exists, he says, has its cause, and
this cause may be one or many. If it is one, then we have what we are looking
for: God, the unitary being to whom all other beings owe their origin. If it is
manifold, there are three possibilities: (1) The manifold may depend on unity
as its cause; or (2) Each thing composing the manifold may be self-caused; or
(3) Each thing may owe its existence to all the other things. The first case is
identical with the hypothesis that everything proceeds from a single cause; for
to depend on several causes, all of which depend on a single cause, means to
depend on this single cause. In the second case, we must assume that there is a
power, force, or faculty of self-existence common to all the particular causes
assumed by the hypothesis; a power in which all participate and are comprised.
But that would give us what we had in the first case, an absolute unitary cause.
The third supposition, which makes each of the 'first causes' depend on all the
rest, is absurd; for we cannot hold that a thing has for its cause and
condition of existence a thing of which it is itself the cause and condition.
Hence we are compelled to believe in a being which is the cause of every
existing thing, without being caused by anything itself, and which for
vi |
"It would be an easy matter to deduce pantheism from the arguments of the Monologium. Anselmus, it is true, protests against such an interpretation of his theology. With St. Augustine he assumes that the world is created ex nihilo. But though accepting this teaching, he modifies it. Before the creation, he says, things did not exist by themselves, independently of God; hence we say they were derived from non-being. But they existed eternally for God and in God, as ideas; they existed before their creation in the sense that the Creator foresaw them and predestined them for existence.
"The existence of God, the unitary and absolute cause
of the world, being proved, the question is to determine his nature and
attributes. God's perfections are like human perfections; with this difference,
however, that they are essential to him, which is not the case with us. Man has
received a share of certain perfections, but there is no necessary correlation
between him and these perfections; it would have been possible for him not to
receive them; he could have existed without them. God, on the contrary, does
not get his perfections from without: he has not received them, and we cannot
say that he has them; he is and must be everything that these perfections
imply; his attributes are identical with his essence. Justice, an attribute of
God, and God are not two separate things. We cannot say of God that he has
justice or goodness; we cannot even say that be is just; for to be just is to
participate in justice after the manner of creatures. God is justice as such,
goodness as such, wisdom as such, happiness as such, truth as such, being as
such. Moreover, all of God's attributes constitute but a single attribute, by
virtue of the unity of his essence (
"All this is pure Platonism. But, not content with
spiritualising theism, Anselmus really discredits it when, like a new
Carneades, he enumerates the difficulties which he finds in the conception. God
is a simple being and at the same time eternal, that is, diffused over infinite
points of time; he is omnipresent, that is,
vii |
"The most formidable theological antinomy is the
doctrine of the trinity of persons in the unity of the divine essence. The Word
is the object of eternal thought; it is God in so far as he is thought,
conceived, or comprehended by himself. The Holy Spirit is the love of God for
the Word, and of the Word for God, the love which God bears himself. But is
this explanation satisfactory? And does it not sacrifice the dogma which it
professes to explain to the conception of unity? St. Anselmus
sees in the Trinity and the notion of God insurmountable difficulties and
contradictions, which the human mind cannot reconcile. In his discouragement be
is obliged to confess, with Scotus Erigena, St. Augustine, and the Neo-Platonists, that no human word can
adequately express the essence of the All-High. Even the words 'wisdom' (
"The Proslogium sive Fides quoerens intellectum
has the same aim as the Monologium: to prove the existence of God. Our
author draws the elements of his argument from St. Augustine
and Platonism. He sets out from the idea of a perfect being, from which he
infers the existence of such a being. We have in ourselves, he says, the idea
of an absolutely perfect being. Now, perfection implies existence. Hence God
exists. This argument, which has been termed the ontological argument,
found an opponent worthy of Anselmus in Gaunilo, a monk of Marmoutiers in
viii |
"The rationalistic tendency which we have just noticed
in the Monologium and the Proslogium meets us again in the Cur
Deus Homo? Why did God become man? The first word of the title sufficiently
indicates the philosophical trend of the treatise. The object is to search for
the causes of the incarnation. The incarnation, according to St. Anselmus, necessarily foIlows from the necessity of
redemption. Sin is an offence against the majesty of God. In spite of his
goodness, God cannot pardon sin without compounding with honor and justice. On
the other hand, he cannot revenge himself on man for his offended honor; for
sin is an offence of infinite degree and therefore demands infinite
satisfaction; which means that he must either destroy humanity or inflict upon
it the eternal punishments of hell. Now, in either case, the goal of creation,
the happiness of his creatures, would be missed and the honor of the Creator
compromised. There is but one way for God to escape this dilemma without
affecting his honor, and that is to arrange for some kind of satisfaction.
He must have infinite satisfaction, because the offence is immeasurable. Now,
in so far as man is a finite being and incapable of satisfying divine justice
in an infinite measure, the infinite being himself must take the matter in
charge; he must have recourse to substitution. Hence, the necessity of
the incarnation. God becomes man in Christ; Christ suffers and dies in
our stead; thus he acquires an infinite merit and the right to an equivalent
recompense. But since the world belongs to the Creator, and nothing can be
added to its treasures, the recompense which by right belongs to Christ
ix |
"Theological criticism has repudiated Anselmus's theory, which bears the stamp of the spirit of chivalry and of feudal customs. But, notwithstanding the attacks of a superficial rationalism, there is an abiding element of truth in it: over and above each personal and variable will there is an absolute, immutable, and incorruptible will, called justice, honor, and duty, in conformity with the customs of the times."
1 From Weber's History of Philosophy. Trans. by F. Thilly. New York Scribner's. Price, $2 50.