|
The Riddles of Philosophy
The Radical World Conceptions
At the beginning of the forties of the last century a man who had
previously thoroughly and intimately penetrated the world conceptions
of Hegel, now forcefully attacked them. This man was Ludwig
Feuerbach (1804 1872). The declaration of war against the
philosophy in which he had grown up is given in a radical form in his
essay, Preliminary Theses for the Reformation of Philosophy
(1842), and Principle of the Philosophy of the Future
(1843). The further development of his thoughts can be followed in
his other writings, The Essence of Christianity (1841), The
Nature of Religion (1845), and Theogony (1857).
In the activity of Ludwig Feuerbach a process is repeated in the field
of the science of the spirit that had happened almost a century
earlier (1759) in the realm of natural science through the activity of
Caspar Friedrich Wolff. Wolff's work had meant a reform of the
idea of evolution in the field of biology. How the idea of evolution
was understood before Wolff can be most distinctly learned from the
views of Albrecht von Haller, a man who opposed the reform of
this conception most vehemently. Hailer, who is quite rightly
respected by physiologists as one of the most significant spirits of
this science, could not conceive the development of a living being in
any other form than that in which the germ already contains all parts
that appear in the course of life, but on a small scale and perfectly
pre-formed. Evolution, then, is supposed to be an unfolding of
something that was there in the first place but was hidden from
perception because of its smallness, or for other reasons. If this
view is consistently upheld, there is no development of anything new.
What happens is merely that something that is concealed, encased, is
continuously brought to the light of day. Hailer stood quite
rigorously for this view. In the first mother, Eve, the whole human
race was contained, concealed on a small scale. The human germs have
only been unfolded in the course of world history. The same conception
is also expressed by the philosopher Leibniz (1646 1716):
So I should think that the souls, which some day will be human souls,
have been in the seed stage, as it is also with those of other
species; that they have existed in the form of organized things in our
forefathers as far back as Adam, that is to say, since the beginning
of things.
Wolff opposed this idea of evolution with one of his own in Theoria
Generationis, which appeared in 1759. He proceeded from the
supposition that the members of an organism that appear in the course
of life have not existed previously but come into being at the moment
they become perceptible as real new formations. Wolff showed that the
egg contains nothing of the form of the developed organism but that
its development constitutes a series of new formations. This view made
the conception of a real becoming possible, for it showed how
something comes into being that had not previously existed and that
therefore comes to be in the true sense of the word.
Hailer's view really denies becoming as it admits only a
continuous process of becoming visible of something that had
previously existed. This scientist had opposed the idea of Wolff with
the peremptory decree, There is no becoming (Nulla est
epigenesis). He had, thereby, actually brought about a situation
in which Wolff s view remained unconsidered for decades. Goethe blames
this encasement theory for the resistance with which his endeavors to
explain living beings was met. He had attempted to comprehend the
formations in organic nature through the study of the process of their
development, which he understood entirely in the sense of a true
evolution, according to which the newly appearing parts of an organism
have not already had a previously concealed existence, but do indeed
come into being when they appear. He writes in 1817 that this
attempt, which was a fundamental presupposition of his essay on the
metamorphosis of plants written in 1790, was received in a cold,
almost hostile manner, but such reluctance was quite natural. The
encasement theory, the concept of pre-formation, of a
successive development of what had existed since Adam's times, had in
general taken possession even of the best minds.
One could see a remnant of the old encasement theory even in Hegel's
world conception. The pure thought that appears in the human mind was
to have been encased in all phenomena before it came to its
perceptible form of existence in man. Before nature and the individual
spirit, Hegel places his pure thought that should be, as it were,
the representation of God as he was according to his eternal
essence before the creation of the world. The development of the
world is, therefore, presented as an unwrapping of pure thought. The
protest of Ludwig Feuerbach against Hegel's world conception was
caused by the fact that Feuerbach was unable to acknowledge the
existence of the spirit before its real appearance in man, just
as Caspar Friedrich Wolff had been unable to admit that the parts of
the living organism should have been pre-formed in the egg. Just as
Wolff saw spontaneous formations in the organs of the developed
organism, so did Feuerbach with respect to the individual spirit of
man. This spirit is in no way there before its perceptible existence;
it comes into being only in the moment it appears. According to
Feuerbach, it is unjustified to speak of an all-embracing spirit, of a
being in which the individual spirit has its roots. No reason-endowed
being exists prior to its appearance in the world that would shape
matter and the perceptible world, and in this way cause the appearance
of man as its visible afterimage. What exists before the development
of the human spirit consists of mere matter and blind forces that form
a nervous system out of themselves concentrated in the brain. In the
brain something comes into existence that is a completely
new formation, something that has never been before: the human
soul, endowed with reason. For such a world conception there is no
possibility to derive the processes and things from a spiritual
originator because, according to this view, a spiritual being is a new
formation through the organization of the brain. If man projects a
spiritual element into the external world, then he imagines
arbitrarily that a being like the one that is the cause of his own
actions exists outside of himself and rules the world. Any spiritual
primal being must first be created by man through his fantasy; the
things and processes of the world give us no reason to assume its
original existence. It is not the original spirit being that has
created man after his image, but man has formed a fantasy of such a
primal entity after his own image. This is Feuerbach's conviction.
Man's knowledge of God is man's knowledge of himself, of his own
nature. Only the unity of being and consciousness is truth. Where
God's consciousness is, there is also God's being: it is,
therefore, in man (The Essence of Christianity, 1841). Man
does not feel strong enough to rest within himself; he therefore
created an infinite being after his own image to revere and to
worship. Hegel's world conception had eliminated all other qualities
from the supreme being, but it had retained the element of reason.
Feuerbach removes this element also and with this step he removes the
supreme being itself. He replaces the wisdom of God completely by the
wisdom of the world. As a necessary turning point in the development
of world conception, Feuerbach declares the open confession and
admission that the consciousness of God is nothing but the
consciousness of humanity, and that man is incapable of
thinking, divining, imagining, feeling, believing, willing, loving and
worshipping as an absolute divine being any other being than the
human being. There is an observation of nature and an
observation of the spirit, but there is no observation of the nature
of God. Nothing is real but the factual.
The real in its reality, or as real, is the real as the object of the
senses, the sensual. Truth, reality and sensuality are
identical. Only a sensual being is a true, a real being. Only through
the senses is an object given in the true sense of the word, not
through thinking by itself. The object that is given in thinking, or
identical with it, is only thought.
Indeed, this can be summed up as follows. The phenomenon of thinking
appears in the human organism as a new formation, but we are not
justified to imagine that this thought had existed before its
appearance in any form invisibly encased in the world. One should not
attempt to explain the condition of something actually given by
deriving it from something that is assumed as previously existing.
Only the factual is true and divine, what is immediately sure of
itself, that-which directly speaks for and convinces of itself, that
which immediately effects the assertion of its existence, what is
absolutely decided, incapable of doubt, clear as sunlight. But only
the sensual is of such a clarity. Only where the sensual begins does
all doubt and quarrel cease. The secret of immediate knowledge is
sensuality. Feuerbach's credo has its climax in the words,
To make philosophy the concern of humanity was my first
endeavor, but whoever decides upon a path in this direction will
finally be led with necessity to make man the concern of
philosophy. The new philosophy makes man, and with him
nature as the basis of man, the only universal and ultimate object of
philosophy; it makes an anthropology that includes physiology in it
the universal science.
Feuerbach demands that reason is not made the basis of departure at
the beginning of a world conception but that it should be considered
the product of evolution, as a new formation in the human organism in
which it makes its actual appearance. He has an aversion to any
separation of the spiritual from the physical because it can be
understood in no other way than as a result of the development of the
physical.
When the psychologist says, I distinguish myself from my
body, he says as much as when the philosopher in logic or
metaphysics says, I leave human nature unconsidered. Is it
possible to leave your own nature out of consideration? Are you not
doing so as a human being? Do you think without a head? Thoughts are
departed souls. All right, but is not even a departed soul still a
faithful picture of a human being who was once in the flesh? Do not
even the most general metaphysical concepts of being and essence
change as the real being and essence of man changes? What does I
leave human nature out of consideration, then mean? Nothing more
than this: I leave man unconsidered so far as he is the object of my
consciousness and of my thinking, but not the man who lies behind my
consciousness; that is to say, not my own nature to which my process
of abstraction also is bound whether I like it or not. So, as a
psychologist, you may disregard your body, but in your nature you are
intimately linked to it, that is, you think yourself as
distinguishable from your body but you are not at all really
different from it because of this thought. . . . Was Lichtenberg not
right when he maintained that one really should not say, I
think, but, It thinks? If, indeed, the I
think now distinguishes itself from the body, does that force us
to conclude that the process that is expressed in the words, It
thinks, the involuntary element of our thinking, the root and
the basis of the I think, is also distinct from the body?
How is it, then, that we cannot think at all times, that the thoughts
are not at our disposal whenever we choose? Why do we often fail to
make headway with some intellectual work in spite of the greatest
exertion of our will until some external occasion, often no more than
a change in the weather, sets our thoughts afloat again? This is
caused by the fact that our thought process is also an organic
activity. Why must we often carry some thoughts with us for years
before they become clear and distinct to us? For the reason that
our thoughts also are subject to an organic development, that our
thoughts also must have their time to mature as well as the fruits in
the field or the child in the mother's womb.
Feuerbach drew attention to Georg Christoph Lichtenberg, a
thinker who died in 1799 and who must be considered a precursor of a
world conception that found expression in thinkers like Feuerbach.
Lichtenberg's stimulating and thought-provoking conceptions were less
fruitful for the nineteenth century probably because the powerful
thought structures of Fichte, Schelling and Hegel overshadowed
everything. They overshadowed the spiritual development to such a
degree that ideas that were expressed aphoristically as strokes of
lightning, even if they were as brilliant as Lichtenberg's, could be
overlooked. We only have to be reminded of a few statements of this
important person to see that in the thought movement introduced by
Feuerbach the spirit of Lichtenberg experiences a revival.
God created man after his image, which probably means that man created
God after his own image.
Our world is going to be so sophisticated one day that it will be as
ridiculous to believe in God as it is nowadays to believe in ghosts.
Is our concept of God really anything but a personified mystery?
The conception that we form of a soul is very much like that of a
magnet in the earth. It is merely a picture. It is an innate trick in
man to think everything in this form.
Rather than to claim that the world is reflected in us, we should say
that our reason is reflected in the world. We just cannot help
discovering order and wisdom in the world; it follows from the nature
of our thought faculty. But it does not necessarily follow that what
we must think should really be so. . . . In this way, then, no God can
be proven.
We become aware of certain conceptions that do not depend on us; then
there are others of which we at least think that they depend on us.
Where is the boundary line between them? We only know that our
perceptions, conceptions and thoughts are there. It thinks, one
should say, just as one says, It rains, or, Thought strikes
as one says, Lightning strikes.
If Lichtenberg had combined such original flashes of thought with the
ability to develop a harmoniously rounded world conception, he could
not have remained unnoticed to the degree that he did. In order to
form a world conception, it is not only necessary to show superiority
of mind, as Lichtenberg did, but also the ability to form ideas in
their interconnection in all directions and to round them plastically.
This faculty he lacked. His superiority is expressed in an excellent
judgment concerning the relation of Kant to his contemporaries:
I believe that just as the followers of Mr. Kant always charge their
opponents with not understanding him, there are also some among them
who believe that Mr. Kant must be right because they understand him.
His mode of conception is new and different from the usual one, and,
if one now suddenly has begun to understand it, one is inclined to
accept it as truth, especially since he has so many ardent followers.
But one should always consider that this understanding is not as yet a
reason to believe it to be true. I believe that most of Kant's
followers, overwhelmed by the joy of having understood an abstract and
obscurely presented system, were also convinced that this system had
been proven.
How akin in spirit Feuerbach could feel to Lichtenberg becomes
especially clear if one compares the views of both thinkers with
respect to the relation of their world conceptions to practical life.
The lectures Feuerbach gave to a number of students during the winter
of 1848 on The Nature of Religion closed with these words:
I only wish that I have not failed in the task that I set for myself
as I expressed it in the first hours, namely, to convert you from
friends of God to friends of men, from believers into thinkers, from
praying men to working men, from adherents to a supersensible realm to
students of this world, from being Christians, who according to their
own confession and admission are half animal and half angel, into
human beings, into entirely human beings.
Whoever, like Feuerbach, bases all world conception on the knowledge
of nature and man, must also reject all direction and duties in the
field of morality that are derived from a realm other than man's
natural inclinations and abilities, or that set aims that do not
entirely refer to the sensually perceptible world. My right
is my lawfully recognized desire for happiness; my duty is
the desire for happiness of others that I am compelled to
recognize. Not in looking with expectation toward a world beyond
do I learn what I am to do, but through the contemplation of this one.
Whatever energy I spend to fulfill any task that refers to the next
world, I have robbed from this world for which I am exclusively meant.
Concentration on this world is, therefore, what
Feuerbach demands. We can read similar expressions in Lichtenberg's
writings. But just such passages in Lichtenberg are always mixed with
elements that show how rarely a thinker who lacks the ability to
develop his ideas in himself harmoniously succeeds in following an
idea into its last consequences. Lichtenberg does, indeed, demand
concentration on this world, but he mixes conceptions that refer to
the next even into the formulation of this demand.
I believe that many people, in their eagerness for an education for
heaven, forget the one that is necessary for the earth. I should
think that man would act wisest if he left the former entirely to
itself. For if we have been placed into this position by a wise
being, which cannot be doubted, then we should do the best we can and
not allow ourselves to be dazzled by revelations. What man needs to
know for his happiness he certainly does know without any more
revelations than he possesses according to his own nature.
Comparisons like this one between Lichtenberg and Feuerbach are
significantly instructive for the historical evolution of man's world
conception. They show most distinctly the direction in which these
personalities advance because one can learn from them the change that
has been wrought by the time interval that lies between them.
Feuerbach went through Hegel's philosophy. He derived the strength
from this experience to develop his own opposing view. He no longer
felt disturbed by Kant's question of whether we are in fact entitled
to attribute reality to the world that we perceive, or whether this
world merely existed in our minds. Whoever upholds the second
possibility can project into the true world behind the perceptual
representations all sorts of motivating forces for man's actions. He
can admit a supernatural world order as Kant had done. But whoever,
like Feuerbach, declares that the sensually perceptible alone is real
must reject every supernatural world order. For him there is no
categorical imperative that could somehow have its origin in a
transcendent world; for him there are only duties that result from the
natural drives and aims of man.
To develop a world conception that was as much the opposite of Hegel's
as that of Feuerbach, a personality was necessary that was as
different from Hegel as was Feuerbach. Hegel felt at home in the midst
of the full activity of his contemporary life. To influence the actual
life of the world with his philosophical spirit appeared to him a most
attractive task. When he asked for his release from his professorship
at Heidelberg in order to accept another chair in Prussia, he
confessed that he was attracted by the expectation of finding a sphere
of activity where he was not entirely limited to mere teaching, but
where it would also be possible for him to affect the practical life.
It would be important for him to have the expectation of moving,
with advancing age, from the precarious function of teaching
philosophy at a university to another activity and to become useful in
such a capacity.
A man who has the inclinations and convictions of a thinker must live
in peace with the shape that the practical life of his time has taken
on. He must find the ideas reasonable by which this life is permeated.
Only from such a conviction can he derive the enthusiasm that makes
him want to contribute to the consolidation of its structure.
Feuerbach was not kindly inclined toward the life of his time. He
preferred the restfulness of a secluded place to the bustle of what
was for him modern life. He expresses himself distinctly
on this point:
I shall never, at any rate, be reconciled with the life in the city.
To go from time to time into the city to teach there, that I consider,
after the impressions I have already stated here, to be good and
indeed my duty, but then I must go back again into the solitude of the
country to study and rest there in the arms of nature. My next task is
to prepare my lectures as my audience wants them, or to prepare my
father's papers for print.
From his seclusion Feuerbach believed himself to be best able to judge
what was not natural with regard to the shape that the actual human
life assumed. To cleanse life from these illusions, and what was
carried into it by human illusions, was what Feuerbach considered to
be his task. To do this he had to keep his distance from life as much
as possible. He searched for the true life but he could not find it in
the form that life had taken through the civilization of the time. How
sincere he was with his concentration on this world is
shown by a statement he made concerning the March revolution. This
revolution seemed to him a fruitless enterprise because the
conceptions that were behind it still contained the old belief in a
world beyond.
The March revolution was a child of the Christian belief, even if it
was an illegitimate one. The constitutionalists believed that the Lord
only had to say, Let there be freedom! Let there be right!
and right and freedom would be there. The republicans believed that
all they had to do was to will a republic to call it to life.
They believed, therefore, in the creation of a republic out of
nothing. The constitutionalists transplanted the idea of the
Christian world-miracles to the field of politics; the republicans,
that of the Christian miracle of action.
Only a personality who is convinced that he carries within him the
harmony of life that man needs can, in the face of the deep hostility
that existed between him and the real world, utter the hymns in praise
of reality that Feuerbach expressed. Such a conviction rings out of
words like these:
Lacking any expectation for the next world, I can hold myself in this
one in the vale of tears of German politics and European political
life in general, alive and in mental sanity, only by making the
present age into an object of Aristophanic laughter.
Only a personality like this could search for all those forces in man
himself that the others wanted to derive from external powers.
The birth of thought in the Greek world conception had had the effect
that man could no longer feel himself as deeply rooted in the world as
had been possible with the old consciousness in the form of picture
conceptions. This was the first step in the process that led to the
formation of an abyss between man and the world. A further stage in
this process consisted in the development of the mode of thinking of
modern natural science. This development tore nature and the human
soul completely apart. On the one side, a nature picture had to arise
in which man in his spiritual-psychical essence was not to be found,
and on the other, an idea of the human soul from which no bridge led
into nature. In nature one found law-ordered necessity. Within its
realm there was no place for the elements that the human soul finds
within: The impulse for freedom, the sense for a life that is rooted
in a spiritual world and is not exhausted within the realm of sensual
existence. Philosophers like Kant escaped the dilemma only by
separating both worlds completely, finding a knowledge in the one, and
in the other, belief. Goethe, Schiller, Fichte, Schelling and Hegel
conceived the idea of the self-conscious soul to be so comprehensive
that it seemed to have its root in a higher spirit nature. In
Feuerbach, a thinker arises who, through the world picture that can be
derived from the modern mode of conception of natural science, feels
compelled to deprive the human soul of every trait contradictory to
the nature picture. He views the human soul as a part of nature. He
can only do so because, in his thoughts, he has first removed
everything in the soul that disturbed him in his attempt to
acknowledge it as a part of nature. Fichte, Schelling and Hegel took
the self-conscious soul for what it was; Feuerbach changes it into
something he needs for his world picture. In him, a mode of conception
makes its appearance that is overpowered by the nature picture. This
mode of thinking cannot master both parts of the modern world picture,
the picture of nature and that of the soul. For this reason, it leaves
one of them, the soul picture, completely unconsidered. Wolff's idea
of new formation introduces fruitful thought impulses to
the nature picture. Feuerbach utilizes these impulses for the
spirit-science that can only exist, however, by not admitting the
spirit at all. Feuerbach initiates a trend of modern philosophy that
is helpless in regard to the most powerful impulse of the modern soul
life, namely, man's active self-consciousness. In this current of
thought, that impulse is dealt with, not merely as an incomprehensible
element, but in a way that avoids the necessity of facing it in its
true form, changing it into a factor of nature, which, to an unbiased
observation, it really is not.
God was my first thought, reason my second and man my
third and last one. With these words Feuerbach describes the
path along which he had gone, from a religious believer to a follower
of Hegel's philosophy, and then to his own world conception. Another
thinker, who, in 1834, published one of the most influential books of
the century, The Life of Jesus, could have said the same thing
of himself. This thinker was David Friedrich Strauss (1808
1874). Feuerbach started with an investigation of the human soul and
found that the soul had the tendency to project its own nature into
the world and to worship it as a divine primordial being. He attempted
a psychological explanation for the genesis of the concept of God. The
views of Strauss were caused by a similar aim. Unlike Feuerbach,
however, he did not follow the path of the psychologist but that of
the historian. He did not, like Feuerbach, choose the concept of God
in general in its all-embracing sense for the center of his
contemplation, but the Christian concept of the God
incarnate, Jesus. Strauss wanted to show how humanity arrived at
this conception in the course of history. That the supreme divine
being reveals itself to the human spirit was the conviction of Hegel's
world conception. Strauss had accepted this, too. But, in his opinion,
the divine idea, in all its perfection, cannot realize itself in an
individual human being. The individual person is always merely an
imperfect imprint of the divine spirit. What one human being lacks in
perfection is presented by another. In examining the whole human race
one will find in it, distributed over innumerable individuals, all
perfection's belonging to the deity. The human race as a whole, then,
is God made flesh, God incarnate. This is, according to Strauss, the
true thinker's concept of Jesus. With this viewpoint Strauss sets out
to criticize the Christian concept of the God incarnate. What,
according to this idea, is distributed over the whole human race,
Christianity attributes to one personality who is supposed to have
existed once in the course of history.
The quality and function, which the doctrine of the Church attributes
to Christ, are contradictory to each other if applied to one
individual, one God incarnate; in the idea of the human race,
they harmonize with one another.
Supported by careful investigations concerning the historical
foundation of the Gospels, Strauss attempts to prove that the
conceptions of Christianity are a result of religious fantasy. Through
this faculty the religious truth that the human race is God incarnate
was dimly felt, but it was not comprehended in clear concepts but
merely expressed in poetic form, in a myth. For Strauss, the story of
the Son of God thus becomes a myth in which the idea of humanity was
poetically treated long before it was recognized by thinkers in the
form of pure thought. Seen from this viewpoint, all miraculous
elements of the history of Christianity become explainable without
forcing the historian to take refuge in the trivial interpretation
that had previously often been accepted. Earlier interpretations had
often seen in those miracles intentional deceptions and fraudulent
tricks to which either the founder of the religion himself had
allegedly resorted in order to achieve the greatest possible effect of
his doctrine, or which the apostles were supposed to have invented for
this purpose. Another view, which wanted to see all sorts of natural
events in the miracles, was also thereby eliminated. The miracles are
now seen as the poetic dress for real truths. The story of humanity
rising above its finite interests and everyday life to the knowledge
of divine truth and reason is represented in the picture of the dying
and resurrected saviour. The finite dies to be resurrected as the
infinite.
We have to see in the myths of ancient peoples a manifestation of the
picture consciousness of primeval times out of which the consciousness
of thought experience developed. A feeling for this fact arises in the
nineteenth century in a personality like Strauss. He wants to gain an
orientation concerning the development and significance of the life of
thought by concentrating on the connection of world conception with
the mythical thinking of historical times. He wants to know in what
way the myth-making imagination still affects modern world conception.
At the same time, he aspires to see the human self-consciousness
rooted in an entity that lies beyond the individual personality by
thinking of all humanity as a manifestation of the deity. In this
manner, he gains a support for the individual human soul in the
general soul of humanity that unfolds in the course of historical
evolution.
Strauss becomes even more radical in his book, The Christian
Doctrine in the Course of Its Historical Development and Its Struggle
with Modern Science, which appeared in the years 1840 and 1841.
Here he intends to dissolve the Christian dogmas in their poetic form
so as to obtain the thought content of the truths contained in them.
He now points out that the modern consciousness is incompatible with
the consciousness that clings to the old mythological picture
representation of the truth.
May, then, the believers allow the knowers to go their own way
unmolested and vice versa; we do not deprive them of their belief; let
them grant us our philosophy, and, if the super-pious should succeed
in ejecting us from their church, we shall consider that as a gain.
Enough wrong compromises have now been attempted; only the separation
of the opposite camps can now lead us ahead.
These views of Strauss produced an enormous uproar. It was deeply
resented that those representing the modern world conception were no
longer satisfied in attacking only the basic religious conceptions in
general, but, equipped with all scientific means of historical
research, attempted to eliminate the irrelevancy about which
Lichtenberg had once said that it consisted of the fact that
human nature had submitted even to the yoke of a book.
He continued:
One cannot imagine anything more horrible, and this example alone
shows what a helpless creature man really is in concreto,
enclosed as he really is in this two-legged vessel of earth, water
and salt. If it were ever possible that reason could have a despotic
throne erected, a man who seriously wanted to contradict the
Copernican system through the authority of a book would have to be
hanged. To read in a book that it originates from God is not a proof
as yet that it really does. It is certain, however, that our reason
has its origin in God no matter in what sense one takes the word God.
Reason punishes, where it rules, only through the natural consequences
of a transgression or through instruction, if instruction can be
called punishment.
Strauss was discharged from his position as a tutor at the Seminary of
Tuebingen because of his book, The Life of Jesus, and when he
then accepted a professorship in theology at the University of Zurich,
the peasants came to meet him with threshing flails in order to make
the position of the dissolver of the myth impossible and to force his
retirement.
Another thinker, Bruno Bauer (1809 1882), in his criticism of
the old world conception from the standpoint of the new, went far
beyond the aim that Strauss had set for himself. He held the same view
as Feuerbach, that man's nature is also his supreme being and any
other kind of a supreme being is only an illusion created after man's
image and set above himself. But Bauer goes further and expresses this
opinion in a grotesque form. He describes how he thinks the human ego
came to create for itself an illusory counter-image, and he uses
expressions that show they are not inspired by the wish for an
intimate understanding of the religious consciousness as was the case
with Strauss. They have their origin in the pleasure of destruction.
Bauer says:
The all-devouring ego became frightened of itself; it did not dare to
consider itself as everything and as the most general power, that is
to say, it still kept the form of the religious spirit and thus
completed its self-alienation in setting its own general power against
itself in fear and trembling for its own preservation and salvation.
Bruno Bauer is a personality who sets out to test his impetuous
thinking critically against everything in existence. That thinking is
destined to penetrate to the essence of things is a conviction he
adopted from Hegel's world conception, but he does not, like Hegel,
tend to let thinking lead to results and a thought structure. His
thinking is not productive, but critical. He would have felt a
definite thought or a positive idea as a limitation. He is unwilling
to limit the power of critical thought by taking his departure from a
definite point of view as Hegel had done.
Critique is, on the one hand, the last act of a definite philosophy,
which through this act frees itself from the limitation of a positive
determination, still curtailed in its generality. It is, therefore, on
the other hand, the presupposition without which philosophy cannot be
raised to the last level of generality of the self-consciousness.
This is the credo of the Critique of World Conception to which
Bruno Bauer confesses. This critique does not believe in
thoughts and ideas but in thinking alone. Only now has man been
discovered, announces Bauer triumphantly, for now man is bound
by nothing except his thinking. It is not human to surrender to a
non-human element, but to work everything out in the melting pot of
thinking. Man is not to be the afterimage of another being, but above
all, he is to be a human being, and he can become human
only through his thinking. The thinking man is the true man. Nothing
external, neither religion nor right, neither state nor law, etc., can
make him into a human being, but only his thinking. The weakness of a
thinking that strives to reach the self-consciousness but cannot do so
is demonstrated in Bauer.
Feuerbach had declared the human being to be man's supreme
being; Bruno Bauer maintained that he had discovered it for the first
time through his critique of world conception; Max Stirner
(1806 1856) set himself the task of approaching this
human being completely without bias and without
presupposition in his book, The Only One and His Possession,
which appeared in 1845. This is Stirner's judgment:
With the power of desperation, Feuerbach grasps at the entire content
of Christianity, not in order to throw it away, but, on the contrary,
in order to seize it, to draw upon this content for so long and so
ardently desired and yet always so remote, with a last effort down
from heaven, to have and to hold onto it forever. Is this not the
clutch of last despair, a matter of life and death, and is it not at
the same time the Christian yearning and passionate desire for the
beyond? The hero does not mean to depart into the beyond, but to draw
the beyond down to himself so that it should turn into this
world. Has not all the world since then been screaming more or
less consciously, This world is all that matters; heaven must
come down to earth and must be felt here already?
Stirner opposes the view of Feuerbach with his violent contradiction:
The highest being, to be sure, is man's being, but exactly because it
is his being and not he, himself, is it a matter of complete
indifference whether we contemplate it outside man, considering it as
God, or whether we find it in him and call it the nature of
man, or the human being. I am neither God nor the
human being, neither the highest being nor my own being, and
for this reason, it is fundamentally of no importance whether I think
this nature within myself or without. We do, indeed, always think the
supreme being in both forms of beyondness, in the inward one as well
as in the outward one at the same time, for the spirit of
God is, according to Christian conception, also our
spirit and dwelleth within us. This spirit dwells in
heaven and within us. We, poor things, are nothing but his
dwelling place and if Feuerbach now goes about and
destroys his heavenly habitations and forces him bag and baggage to
move into us, then we, as his terrestrial quarters, will become very
badly overcrowded.
The individual human ego does not consider itself from its own
standpoint but from the standpoint of a foreign power. A religious man
claims that there is a divine supreme being whose afterimage is man.
He is possessed by this supreme being. The Hegelian says that there is
a general world reason and it realizes itself to reach its climax in
the human ego. The ego is therefore possessed by this world reason.
Feuerbach maintains that there is a nature of the human being and
every particular person is an individualized afterimage of this
nature. Every individual is thereby possessed by the idea of
the nature of humanity. For only the individual man is
really existing, not the generic concept of humanity by
which Feuerbach replaces the divine being. If, then, the individual
man places the genus man above himself, he abandons
himself to an illusion, just as much as when he feels himself
dependent on a personal God. For Feuerbach, therefore, the
commandments the Christian considers as given by God, and which for
this reason he accepts as valid, change into commandments that have
their validity because they are in accordance with the general idea of
humanity. Man now judges himself morally by asking the question: Do my
actions as an individual correspond to what is adequate to the nature
of humanity in general? For Feuerbach says:
If the essence of humanity is man's supreme being, then the highest
and first law of his practical life must also be the love of man to
man. Homo homini deus est, man is God to man. Ethics is in
itself a divine power. Moral relationships are by themselves truly
religious relationships. Life in general is, in its substantial
connections, of a thoroughly divine nature. Everything that is right,
true and good carries the ground of its salvation in its own
qualities. Friendship is and shall be sacred, as shall be property and
marriage, and sacred shall be the well-being of every man, but sacred
in and for itself.
There are, then, general human powers, and ethics is one of them. It
is sacred in and for itself; the individual has to submit to it. The
individual is not to will what it decides out of its own initiative,
but what follows from the direction of the sacred ethics. The
individual is possessed by this ethics. Stirner characterizes
this view as follows:
The God of all, namely, the human being, has now been elevated to be
the God of the individual, for it is the highest aim of all of us to
be a human being. As no one can entirely become what the idea of
humanity expresses, however, the human being remains for
every individual a sublime beyond, an unattainable supreme being, a
God.
But such a supreme being is also thinking, which has been
elevated to be God by the critique of world conception. Stirner cannot
accept this either.
The critical thinker is afraid of becoming dogmatic, or of
making positive statements. Of course, he would in doing so become the
opposite of a critic, a dogmatist; he would then be as bad as a
dogmatist as he is now good as a critic. . . . There must by no means
be any dogma! This is his dogma. For the critic stays on the same
ground with the dogmatist, namely, on the ground of thought.
Like the dogmatist, he always proceeds from a thought, but he
differs insofar as he abandons the practice of preserving the
principal thought in the process of thinking; he does not allow
this process to become stabilized. He only emphasizes the process of
thinking against the belief in thoughts, the process of the former
against the stagnation of the latter. No thought is safe against
criticism because it is thinking or the thinking spirit itself. . . .
I am no antagonist of criticism, that is to say, I am no dogmatist and
feel that the teeth of the critic that tear the flesh of the dogmatist
do not touch me. If I were a dogmatist, I should place a dogma, a
thought, an idea, a principle, at the beginning, and I should begin
this process as a systematic thinker by spinning it out into a system
that is a thought structure. If, on the other hand, I were a critical
thinker, that is, an opponent of the dogmatist, then I should lead the
fight of free thinking against the enslaved thought. I should defend
thinking against the result of this activity. But I am neither the
champion of thought nor of thinking.
Every thought is also produced by the individual ego of an individual,
even the thought of one's own being, and when man means to know his
own ego and wants to describe it according to its nature, he
immediately brings it into dependence on this nature. No matter what I
may invent in my thinking, as soon as I determine and define myself
conceptually, I make myself the slave of the result of the definition,
the concept. Hegel made the ego into a manifestation of reason, that
is to say, he made it dependent on reason. But all such generalities
cannot be valid with regard to the ego because they all have their
source in the ego. They are caused by the fact that the ego is
deceived by itself. It is really not dependent, for everything on
which it could depend must first be produced by the ego. The ego must
produce something out of itself, set it above itself and allow it to
turn into a spectre that haunts its own originator.
Man, you have bats in your belfry; there is a screw loose in your
head! You imagine big things; you invent a whole world of Gods that is
supposed to be there for your benefit, a realm of spirit for which you
are destined, an ideal that is becoming you. You have an idée
fixe!
In reality, no thinking can approach what lives within me as
I. I can reach everything with my thinking; only my ego is
an exception in this respect. I cannot think it; I can only
experience it. I am not will; I am not idea; I am that no more
than the image of a deity. I make all other things comprehensible to
myself through thinking. The ego I am. I have no need to define
and to describe myself because I experience myself in every moment. I
need to describe only what I do not immediately experience, what is
outside myself. It is absurd that I should also have to conceive
myself as a thought, as an idea, since I always have myself as
something. If I face a stone, I may attempt to explain to myself what
this stone is. What I am myself, I need not explain; it is
given in my life.
Stirner answers to an attack against his book:
The only one is a word and with a word it should be
possible to think something; a word should have a thought
content. But the only one is a thoughtless word; it
does not have a thought content. What then is its content if it is not
thought? It is a content that cannot be there a second time and
therefore is also incapable of being expressed; for if it could
be expressed, really and completely pressed out, then it would be
there a second time; it would be there in the expression. Because the
content of the only one is not a thought content, it is
also unthinkable and ineffable, but because it is ineffable, this
perfectly empty phrase is at the same time not a phrase. Only
when nothing is said of you, when you are simply called, are you
recognized as you. As long as something is said of you, you are
recognized only as this something (human being, spirit, Christian,
etc.). The only one does not contain a statement because
it is only name, saying nothing more than that you are you and
nothing but you; that you are a unique you and you
yourself. Through this, you are without a predicate, and thereby
without quality, calling, legal standing and restriction, and so
forth. (Compare Stirner's Kleine Schriften, edited by J. H.
Mackay, pp. 116.)
Stirner, in an essay written in 1842, The Untrue Principle of Our
Education, or Humanism and Realism, had already expressed his
conviction that thinking cannot penetrate as far as the core of the
personality. He therefore considers it an untrue educational principle
if this core of the personality is not made the objective of
education, but when knowledge as such assumes this position in a
one-sided way.
A knowledge that does not so purge and concentrate itself that it
inspires the will, or in other words, that only weighs me down with
possession and property instead of having become entirely one with me
so that the freely moving ego, unhampered by any cumbersome belongings
travels through the world with an open mind; a knowledge, then, that
has not become personal will make a miserable preparation for
life. . . . If it is the cry of our time, after the freedom of
thought has been obtained, to continue this freedom to its end
through which it turns into the freedom of will so that the
latter can be realized as the aim of a new epoch, then the last aim of
education can no longer be knowledge but a will that is
born out of knowledge, and the revealing expression of the
educational aim is the personal or free man. . . . As in
certain other spheres, so also in that of education, freedom is not
allowed to break forth; the power of opposition is not yielded
the floor: subordination is insisted upon. Only formal and
material drill is the aim of this education; in the menagerie of the
humanists nothing but scholars are produced and in that of
the realists, nothing but "useful citizens. Both then
produce nothing but submissive human beings. Knowledge
must die to be resurrected as will and to restore itself
daily in free personalities.
The personality of the individual human being can alone contain the
source of his actions. The moral duties cannot be commandments that
are given to man from somewhere, but they must be aims that man sets
for himself. Man is mistaken if he believes that he does something
because he follows a commandment of a general code of sacred ethics.
He does it because the life of his ego drives him to it. I do not love
my neighbor because I follow a sacred commandment of neighborly love,
but because my ego draws me to my neighbor. It is not that I am
to love him; I want to love him. What men have wanted
to do they have placed as commandments above themselves. On this
point Stirner can be most easily understood. He does not deny moral
action. What he does deny is the moral commandment. If man
only understands himself rightly, then a moral world order will be the
result of his actions. Moral prescriptions are a spectre, an
idée fixe, for Stirner. They prescribe something at which man
arrives all by himself if he follows entirely his own nature. The
abstract thinkers will, of course, raise the objection, Are
there not criminals? These abstract thinkers anticipate general
chaos if moral prescriptions are not sacred to man. Stirner could
reply to them, Are there not also diseases in nature? Are they
not produced in accordance with eternal unbreakable laws just as
everything that is healthy?
As little as it will ever occur to any reasonable person to reckon the
sick with the healthy because the former is, like the latter, produced
through natural laws, just as little would Stirner count the immoral
with the moral because they both come into being when the individual
is left to himself. What distinguishes Stirner from the abstract
thinkers, however, is his conviction that in human life morality will
be dominating as much as health is in nature, when the decision is
left to the discretion of individuals. He believes in the moral
nobility of human nature, in the free development of morality out of
the individuals. It seems to him that the abstract thinkers do not
believe in this nobility, and he is, therefore, of the opinion that
they debase the nature of the individual to become the slave of
general commandments, the corrective scourges of human action. There
must be much evil depravity at the bottom of the souls of these
moral persons, according to Stirner, because they are so
insistent in their demands for moral prescriptions. They must indeed
be lacking love because they want love to be ordered to them as a
commandment that should really spring from them as spontaneous
impulse.
Only twenty years ago it was possible that the following criticism
could be made in a serious book:
Max Stirner's book, The Only One and His Possession, destroyed
spirit and humanity, right and state, truth and virtue as if they were
idols of the bondage of thought, and confessed without reluctance,
I place nothing above myself! (Heinrich von Treitschke,
Deutsche Geschichte, Part V, pp. 416; 1927.)
This only proves how easily Stirner can be misunderstood as a result
of his radical mode of expression because, to him, the human
individual was considered to be so noble, so elevated, unique and free
that not even the loftiest thought world was supposed to reach up to
it. Thanks to the endeavors of John Henry Mackay, we have today a
picture of his life and his character. In his book, Max Stirner,
His Life and His Work (Berlin, 1898), he has summed up the
complete result of his research extending over many years to arrive at
a characterization of Stirner who was, in Mackay's opinion, The
boldest and most consistent of all thinkers.
Stirner, like other thinkers of modern times, is confronted with the
self-conscious ego, challenging comprehension. Others search for means
to comprehend this ego. The comprehension meets with difficulties
because a wide gulf has opened up between the picture of nature and
that of the life of the spirit. Stirner leaves all that without
consideration. He faces the fact of the self-conscious ego and uses
every means at his disposal to express this fact. He wants to speak of
the ego in a way that forces everyone to look at the ego for himself,
so that nobody can evade this challenge by claiming that the ego is
this or the ego is that. Stirner does not want to point out an idea or
a thought of the ego, but the living ego itself that the personality
finds in itself.
Stirner's mode of conception, as the opposite pole to that of Goethe,
Schiller, Fichte, Schelling and Hegel, is a phenomenon that had to
appear with a certain necessity in the course of the development of
modern world conception. Stirner became aware of the self-conscious
ego with an inescapable, piercing intensity. Every thought production
appeared to him in the same way in which the mythical world of
pictures is experienced by a thinker who wants to seize the world in
thought alone. Against this intensely experienced fact, every other
world content that appeared in connection with the self-conscious ego
faded away for Stirner. He presented the self-conscious ego in
complete isolation.
Stirner does not feel that there could be difficulties in presenting
the ego in this manner. The following decades could not establish any
relationship to this isolated position of the ego. For these decades
are occupied above all with the task of forming the nature picture
under the influence of the mode of thought of natural science. After
Stirner had presented the one side of modern consciousness, the fact
of the self-conscious ego, the age at first withdraws all attention
from this ego and turns to the picture of nature where this
ego is not to be found.
The first half of the nineteenth century had born its world conception
out of the spirit of idealism. Where a bridge is laid to lead to
natural science, as it is done by Schelling, Lorenz Oken (1779 1851)
and Henrik Steffens (1773 1845), it is done from the viewpoint of
the idealistic world conception and in its interest. So little was the
time ready to make thoughts of natural science fruitful for world
conceptions that the ingenious conception of Jean Lamarck pertaining
to the evolution of the most perfect organisms out of the simple one,
which was published in 1809, drew no attention at all. When in 1830
Geoffroy de St. Hilaire presented the idea of a general natural
relationship of all forms of organisms in his controversy with
Couvier, it took the genius of Goethe to see the significance of this
idea. The numerous results of natural science that were contributed in
the first half of the century became new world riddles for the
development of world conception when Charles Darwin in 1859, opened up
new aspects for an understanding of nature with his treatment of the
world of living organisms.
|
Last Modified: 17-Jul-2009 |
The Rudolf Steiner Archive is maintained by:
The e.Librarian:
elibrarian@elib.com
|
|
|
|
|