|
The Riddles of Philosophy
The Struggle Over the Spirit
Hegel felt that with his thought structure he had arrived at the goal
for which the evolution of world conception had been striving since
man had attempted to conquer the enigmatic problems of existence
within the realm of thought experiences. With this feeling he wrote,
toward the end of his Encyclopedia of the Philosophical Sciences,
the following words. The concept of philosophy is the idea
that thinks itself; it is knowing truth. . . . Philosophical
knowledge has in this manner gone back to its beginning, and the
content of logic thus becomes its result as the spiritual
element that has revealed itself as truth, as it is in itself and
for itself.
The experience of itself in thought, according to Hegel, is to give to
the human soul the consciousness of being at its true original source.
In drinking from this source, filling itself with thoughts from it,
the soul is supposed to live in its own true essence and in that of
nature at the same time, for both nature and the soul are
manifestations of thought. Through the phenomena of nature the thought
world looks at the soul, which seizes in itself the creative power of
thought so that it knows itself in union with all world processes. The
soul thus sees its own narrow circle of self-consciousness enlarged
through the fact that the world observes itself consciously in it. The
soul thereby ceases to consider itself merely as something that is
aware of itself in the transitory sensual body between birth and
death. The imperishable spirit, which is not bound to any sensual
existence, knows itself in the soul, and the soul is aware of being
bound to this spirit in an inseparable union.
Let us place ourselves in the position of, the soul of a personality
who could follow Hegel's trend of ideas to the extent that he believed
that he experienced the presence of thought in his consciousness in
the same way as Hegel himself. We can then feel how, for such a soul,
age-old enigmatic questions appear to be placed in a light that can be
highly satisfactory to such an inquirer. Such satisfaction is indeed
apparent, for instance, in the numerous writings of the Hegelian
thinker, Karl Rosenkranz. As we absorb these writings with
concentrated attention (System of Philosophy, 1850;
Psychology, 1844; Critical Explanations of the Hegelian
Philosophy, 1851), we feel ourselves confronted with a personality
who is convinced he has found in Hegel's ideas what can provide a
satisfactory cognitive relation to the world for the human soul.
Rosenkranz can be mentioned in this respect as a significant example
because he is not at all blindly following Hegel every step, but shows
that he is a spirit motivated by the consciousness that Hegel's
position toward world and man contains the possibility of giving a
healthy foundation to a world conception.
What could a thinker like Rosenkranz experience with regard to this
foundation? Since the birth of thought in ancient Greece, and during
centuries of philosophical investigation of the riddles of existence
with which every soul was fundamentally confronted, a number of major
problems have crystallized. In modern times the problem of the
significance, the value and the limits of knowledge has moved, as the
fundamental problem, into the center of philosophical reflection. What
relation has man's perception, conception and thought to the real
world? Can this process of perception and thinking result in a
knowledge that is capable of enlightening man concerning the questions
about which he wants to be enlightened? For a person who thinks like
Hegel, this question answers itself through the implication in Hegel's
thought concept. As he gains hold of thought, he is convinced he
experiences the creative spirit of the world. In this union with
creative thought he feels the value and true significance of
cognition. He cannot ask, What is the meaning of
knowledge? for he experiences this significance as he is engaged
in the act of knowing. Through this fact the Hegelian is directly
opposed to all Kantianism. Witness what Hegel himself has to say
against the Kantian method of investigating cognition before the act
of knowledge has taken place.
A main point of the critical philosophy consists in the fact that
before it sets out to develop a knowledge of God, the essence of
things, etc., it is demanded that the faculty of knowledge must be
investigated as to whether it is capable of doing such things. One
must know the instrument before one undertakes the work that is
to be achieved by means of it. If this instrument should prove
insufficient, all endeavor would be wasted. This thought has appeared
so plausible that it aroused the greatest admiration and
agreement, and led knowledge, motivated by an interest in the objects
of knowledge, back to itself. If, however, one does not want to
deceive oneself with words, it is quite easy to see that other
instruments can be investigated and judged in some other way than by
undertaking the work with them for which they are meant. But knowledge
can be investigated in no other way than in the act of knowledge;
in the case of this so-called instrument, the process to test it
is nothing but knowledge itself. To know before one knows is as absurd
as the wise intention of the scholastic thinker who wanted to learn
to swim before he dared go into the water.
For Hegel, the main point was that the soul should experience itself
as filled with the living world thought. Thus, it grows beyond its
ordinary existence; it becomes, as it were, the vessel in which world
thought, living in thinking, seizes itself in full consciousness. The
soul is not merely felt as a vessel of this world spirit but as an
entity conscious of its union with that spirit. Thus it is, according
to Hegel, not possible to investigate the essence of knowledge. We
must immediately raise ourselves into participation in this essence
through its experience and, with that step, we are directly inside the
process of knowledge. If one stands inside that process, one is in
possession of that knowledge and feels no longer the need to
inquire after its significance. If one cannot take this stand, one
lacks also the ability to investigate it. The Kantian philosophy is an
impossibility for Hegel's world conception because, in order to answer
the question, How is knowledge possible, the soul would
first have to produce knowledge. In that case, the question of its
existence could not be raised beforehand.
In a certain sense Hegel's philosophy amounts to this: He allows the
soul to lift itself to a certain height at which point it grows into
unity with the world. With the birth of thought in Greek philosophy
the soul separated from the world. The soul is felt as in solitude as
opposed to the world. In this seclusion the soul finds itself holding
sway within itself. It is Hegel's intention to bring this experience
of thought to its climax. At the same time he finds the creative world
principle in the highest thought experience. The soul has thus
completed the course of a perfect circle in separating itself at first
from the world in order to search for thought. It feels itself
separated from the world only as long as it recognizes in thought
nothing but thought. It feels united with the world again as it
discovers in thought the original source of the world. Thus, the
circle is closed. Hegel can say, In this manner science has
returned to its beginning.
Seen from such a viewpoint, the other main problems of human knowledge
are set in such a light that one can believe one sees all existence in
one coherent world conception. As a second major problem, one can
consider the question of deity as the ground of the world. The
elevation of the soul that enables the world thought to awaken to
self-knowledge as it lives within the soul is, for Hegel, at the same
time the soul's union with the divine world ground. According to him,
one therefore cannot ask the question, What is the divine
ground of the world? or, What is man's relation toward
it? One can only say, When the soul really experiences
truth in the act of knowledge, it penetrates into this ground of the
world.
A third major question in the above-mentioned sense is the
cosmological problem, that is to say, the problem of the inner essence
of the outer world. This essence can, according to Hegel, be sought
only in thought itself. When the soul arrives at the point of
experiencing thought in itself, it also finds in its self-experience
the form of thought it can recognize as it observes the processes and
entities of the external world. Thus, it can, for instance, find
something in its thought experience of which it knows immediately that
this is the essence of light. As it then turns its eye to nature, it
sees in the external light the manifestation of the thought essence of
light.
In this way, for Hegel, the whole world dissolves into thought entity.
Nature swims, as it were, as a frozen part in the cosmos of thought,
and the human soul becomes thought in the thought world.
The fourth major problem of philosophy, the question of the nature and
destiny of the soul, seems to Hegel's mind satisfactorily answered
through the true progress of thought experience. At first, the soul
finds itself bound to nature. In this connection it does not know
itself in its true entity. It divorces itself from this nature
existence and finds itself then separated in thought, arriving at last
at the insight that it possesses in thought both the true essence of
nature and its own true being as that of the living spirit as it lives
and weaves as a member of this spirit.
All materialism seems to be overcome with this philosophy. Matter
itself appears merely as a manifestation of the spirit. The
human soul may feel itself as becoming and having its being in the
spiritual universe.
In the treatment of the problem of the soul the Hegelian world
conception shows probably most distinctly what is unsatisfactory about
it. Looking at this world conception, the human soul must ask,
Can I really find myself in the comprehensive thought
construction of the world erected by Hegel? We have seen that
all modern world conception must look for a world picture in which the
entity of the human soul finds an adequate place. To Hegel, the whole
world is thought; within this thought the soul also has its
supersensible thought existence. But can the soul be satisfied to be
contained as world thought in the general thought world? This question
arises in thinkers who had been stimulated by Hegel's philosophy in
the middle of the nineteenth century.
What are really the most urgent riddles of the soul? They are the ones
for the answers of which the soul must feel a yearning, expecting from
them the feeling of security and a firm hold in life. There is, to
begin with, the question, What is the human soul
essentially? Is the soul identical with the corporeal existence
and do its manifestations cease with the decay of the body as the
motion of the hands of a clock stop when the clock is taken apart? Or,
is the soul an entity independent of the body, possessing life and
significance in a world apart from that in which the body comes into
being and dissolves into nothing? Connected with these questions is
another problem. How does man obtain knowledge of such a world? Only
in answering this question can man hope to receive light for
the problems of life: Why am I subjected to this or that destiny? What
is the source of suffering? What is the origin of morality?
Satisfaction can be given only by a world conception that offers
answers to the above-mentioned questions and at the same time proves
its right to give such answers.
Hegel offered a world of thoughts. If this world is to be the all
inclusive universe, then the soul is forced to regard itself in its
inner substance as thought. If one seriously accepts this cosmos of
thought, one will find that the individual soul life of man dissolves
in it. One must give up the attempt to explain and to understand this
individual soul life and is forced to say that the significance of the
soul does not rest in its individual experience but in the fact
that it is contained in the general thought world. This is what the
Hegelian world conception fundamentally does say. One should contrast
it with what Lessing had in mind when he conceived the ideas of his
Education of the Human Race. He asked the question of the
significance for the individual human soul beyond the life that
is enclosed between birth and death. In pursuing this thought of
Lessing one can say that the soul after physical death goes through a
form of existence in a world that lies outside the one in which man
lives, perceives and thinks in his body; after an appropriate time,
such a purely spiritual form of experience is followed again by a new
earth life. In this process a world is implied with which the human
soul, as a particular, individual entity, is bound up. Toward this
world the soul feels directed in searching for its own true being.
As soon as one conceives the soul as separated from the connection
with its physical form of existence, one must think of it as belonging
to that same world. For Hegel, however, the life of the soul, in
shedding all individual traits, is absorbed first into the general
thought process of the historical evolution, then into that of the
general spiritual-intellectual world processes. In Hegel's sense, one
solves the riddle of the soul in leaving all individual traits of that
soul out of consideration. The individual is not real, but the
historical process. This is illustrated by the passage toward the end
of Hegel's Philosophy of History:
We have exclusively considered the progress of the concept and had to
renounce the tempting pleasure to depict the fortune, the flourishing
periods of the peoples, the greatness and the beauty of the
individuals, the interest of their destiny in sorrow and joy.
Philosophy has to deal only with the lustre of the idea that is
reflected in world history. Weary of the immediate passions in the
world of reality, philosophy emancipates into contemplation; it is the
interest of philosophy to recognize the course of development of the
self-realization of the idea.
Let us look at Hegel's doctrine of the soul. We find here the
description of the process of the soul's evolution within the body as
natural soul, the development of consciousness of self and
of reason. We then find the soul realizing the ideas of right,
morality and the state in the external world. It is then described how
the soul sees in world history, as a continuous life, what it
thinks as ideas. It is shown how it lives these ideas as art
and religion, and how the soul unites with the truth that thinks
itself, seeing itself in the living creative spirit of the universe.
Every thinker who feels like Hegel must be convinced that the world in
which he finds himself is entirely spirit, that all material existence
is also nothing but a manifestation of the spirit. If such a thinker
searches for the spirit, he will find it essentially as active
thought, as living, creative idea. This is what the soul is
confronted with. It must ask itself if it can really consider
itself as a being that is nothing but thought essence. It can be felt
as the real greatness, the irrefutable element of Hegel's world
conception that the soul, in rising to true thought, feels elevated to
the creative principle of existence. To feel man's relation to the
world in this way was an experience of deep satisfaction to those
personalities who could follow Hegel's thought development.
How can one live with this thought? That was the great riddle
confronting modern world conception. It had resulted from the
continuation of the process begun in Greek philosophy when thought had
emerged and when the soul had thereupon become detached from external
existence. Hegel now has attempted to place the whole range of thought
experience before the soul, to present to the soul, as it were,
everything it can produce as thought out of its depths. In the face of
this thought experience Hegel now demands of the soul that it
recognize itself according to its deepest nature in this experience,
that it feel itself in this element as in its deepest ground.
With this demand of Hegel the human soul has been brought to a
decisive point in the attempt to obtain a knowledge of its own being.
Where is the soul to turn when it has arrived at the element of pure
thought but does not want to remain stationary at this point From the
experience of perception, feeling and will, it proceeds to the
activity of thinking and asks, What will result if I think about
perception, feeling and will? Having arrived at thinking, it is
at first not possible to proceed any further. The soul's attempt in
this direction can only lead to thinking again. Whoever follows
the modern development of philosophy as far as the age of Hegel can
have the impression that Hegel pursues the impulses of this
development to a point beyond which it becomes impossible to go so
long as this process retains the general character exhibited up to
that time. The observation of this fact can lead to the question: If
thinking up to this stage brings philosophy in Hegel's sense to the
construction of a world picture that is spread out before the soul,
has this energy of thinking then really developed everything
that is potentially contained within it? It could be, after all,
that thinking contains more possibilities than that of mere thinking.
Consider a plant, which develops from the root through its stem and
leaves into blossom and fruit. The life of this plant can now be
brought to an end by taking the seed from the fruit and using it as
human food, for instance. But one can also expose the seed of the
plant to the appropriate conditions with the effect that it will
develop into a new plant.
In concentrating one's attention on the significance of Hegel's
philosophy, one can see how the thought picture that man develops of
the world unfolds before him like a plant; one can observe that the
development is brought to the point where the seed, thought, is
produced. But then this process is brought to an end, just as in the
life of the plant whose seed is not developed further in its own
organic function, but is used for a purpose that is as extraneous to
this life as the purpose of human nutrition is to the seed of the
reproductive organs. Indeed, as soon as Hegel has arrived at the point
where thought is developed as an element, he does not continue the
process that brought him to this point. He proceeds from sense
perception and develops everything in the human soul in a process that
finally leads to thought. At this stage he stops and shows how this
element can provide an explanation of the world processes and world
entities. This purpose can indeed be served by thought, just as the
seed of a plant may be used as human food. But should it not be
possible to develop a living element out of thought? Is it not
possible that this element is deprived of its own life through the use
that Hegel makes of it, as the seed of a plant is deprived of its life
when it is used as human food? In what light would Hegel's philosophy
have to appear if it were possibly true that thought can be used for
the enlightenment, for the explanation of the world processes, as a
plant seed can be used for food but only by sacrificing its continued
growth? The seed of a plant, to be sure, can produce only a plant of
the same kind. Thought, however, as a seed of knowledge, could, if
left to its living development, produce something of an entirely new
kind, compared to the world picture from which its evolution would
proceed. As the plant life is ruled by the law of repetition,
so the life of knowledge could be under the law of enhancement
and elevation. It is unthinkable that thought as we employ it for
the explanation of external science should be merely a byproduct of
evolution, just as the use of plant seeds for food is a sidetrack in
the plant's continuous development. One can dismiss ideas of this kind
on the ground that they have their origin in an arbitrary imagination
and that they represent mere possibilities without any value. It is
just as easily understood that the objection can be raised that at the
point at which this idea would be developed we would enter the realm
of arbitrary fantasy. To the observer of the historical development of
the philosophies of the nineteenth century this question can
nevertheless appear in a different light. The way in which Hegel
conceives the element of thought does indeed lead the evolution of
world conception to a dead end. One feels that thought has reached an
extreme; yet, if one wants to introduce this thought in the form in
which it is conceived in the immediate life of knowledge, it becomes a
disappointing failure. There arises a longing for a life that should
spring from the world conception that one has accomplished.
Friedrich Theodor Vischer begins to write his Esthetics in
Hegel's manner in the middle of the nineteenth century. When finished,
it is a work of monumental importance. After its completion he becomes
the most penetrating critic of his own work. If one searches for the
deeper reason for this strange process, one finds that Vischer has
become aware of the fact that, as he had permeated his work with
Hegelian thoughts, he had introduced an element that had become dead,
since it had been taken out of the ground that had provided its life
conditions, just as a plant seed dies when its growth is cut off. A
peculiar perspective is opening before us as we see Hegel's world
conception in this light. The nature of the thought element could
demand to be received as a living seed and, under certain conditions,
to be developed in the soul. It could unfold its possibility by
leading beyond the world picture of Hegel to a world conception in
which the soul could come to a knowledge of its own being with which
it could truly hold its own position in the external world. Hegel has
brought the soul to the point where it can live with the element of
thought; the progress beyond Hegel would lead to the thought's
growth in the soul beyond itself and into a spiritual world.
Hegel understood how the soul magically produces thought within
itself and experiences itself in thought. He left to posterity the
task of discovering by means of living thoughts, which are active in a
truly spiritual world, the real being of the soul that cannot fully
experience itself in the element of mere thought.
It has been shown in the preceding exposition how the development of
modern world conception strives from the perception of thought
toward the experience of thought. In Hegel's world conception
the world seems to stand before the soul as a self-produced thought
experience, but the trend of evolution seems to indicate further
progress. Thought must not become stationary as thought; it must not
be merely thought, not be experienced merely through
thinking; it must awaken to a still higher life.
As arbitrary as all this may appear at first, it is nevertheless the
view that prevails when a more penetrating observation of the
development of modern world conception in the nineteenth century is
made. Such an observation shows how the demands of an age exert their
effect in the deeper strata of the evolution of history. It shows the
aims that men set for themselves as attempts to do justice to
these demands. Men of modern times were confronted with the world
picture of natural science. It was necessary to find conceptions
concerning the life of the soul that could be maintained while this
world picture was sustained. The whole development from Descartes,
Spinoza, Leibniz, Locke, to Hegel, appears as a struggle for such
conceptions. Hegel brings this struggle to a certain conclusion. His
mode of thinking, as he presents the world as thought, appears to be
latent everywhere with his predecessors. He takes the bold step as a
thinker to bring all world conceptions to a climax by uniting them in
a comprehensive thought picture. With him the age has, for the time
being, exhausted the energy of its advancing impulses. What was
formulated above, that is, the demand to experience the life of
thought inwardly, is unconsciously felt. This demand is felt as
a burden on the souls at the time of the middle of the nineteenth
century. People despair of the impossibility of fulfilling this
demand, but they are not fully aware of their despair. Thus, a
stagnation in the philosophical field sets in. The productivity with
respect to philosophical ideas ceases. It would have had to develop in
the indicated direction, but first it seems to be necessary to pause
in deliberation about the achievement that has been attained. Attempts
are made to start from one point or another of the philosophical
predecessors, but the force to continue the world picture of Hegel
fruitfully is lacking.
Witness Karl Rosenkranz's description of the situation in the preface
to his Life of Hegel (1844):
It is not without regret that I part from this work, but it is
necessary to proceed at some time from becoming to
existence. Does it not seem, however, that we are nowadays only
the gravediggers and survivors to set monuments to the philosophers
who were born in the second half of the eighteenth century, and who
died in the first of the nineteenth century? Kant began this march of
death of the German philosophers in 1804. He was followed by Fichte,
Jacobi, Solger, Reinhold, Krause, Schleiermacher, William von
Humboldt, Friedrich Schlegel, Herbart, Baader, Wagner, Windischmann,
Fries, and so many others. . . . Do we see a succeeding generation for
this harvest of death? Are we capable also of sending into the second
half of our century a venerable group of thinkers? Are there living
among our young men those who are inspired to immortal exertion for
speculative contemplation, by Platonic enthusiasm and Aristotelian joy
of painstaking industry? . . . Strangely enough, in our day the
talents seem to be not quite able to hold onto their task. They
are quickly used up and after a few promising flowers, they become
barren and begin to copy and repeat themselves at the very moment
when, after having overcome their still immature, imperfect, one-sided
and stormy youthful attempts, periods of forceful and concentrated
activity should begin. Some of them, full of exaggerated eagerness, go
too far in their quest and must, like Constantin Frantz, take back
partly in later books what they said in earlier ones . . .
It can often be seen that, after the middle of the nineteenth century,
people found themselves forced to subscribe to such a judgment of the
philosophical situation of the time. The excellent thinker, Franz
Brentano, made the following statement in the inaugural speech for his
professorship, Concerning the Reasons for Discouragement in the
Philosophical Field, in 1874:
In the first decades of our century the lecture halls of the German
philosophers were overcrowded; in more recent times, this flood has
been followed by an ebb tide. One often hears that gifted men accuse
the younger generation of lacking the sense for the highest branches
of knowledge. That would be a sad but also an incomprehensible fact.
How could it be that the entire new generation should be inferior' to
the earlier one in spiritual momentum and mobility? It was in reality
not a lack of talent but . . . lack of confidence that had the effect
of decreasing philosophical studies. If the hope for success had come
back, the highest honors in this field would be waiting in vain to be
conquered . . .
In Hegel's lifetime, and for a short time after, there already were
people who felt that his world picture showed its weakness in the very
point that contained its greatness. His world conception leads toward
thought but also forces the soul to consider its nature to be
exhausted in the thought element. If this world conception would bring
thought in the above-mentioned sense to a life of its own, then this
could only happen within the individual soul life; the soul would
thereby find its relation toward the whole cosmos. This was felt, for
instance, by Troxler, but he did not develop the conviction beyond the
state of a dim feeling. In lectures that he gave at the University of
Bern in 1835 he expressed himself as follows:
Not only now but also twenty years ago, we have been living with the
most intimate conviction, and we have tried to show this in writing
and speech, that a philosophy and an anthropology that was to embrace
man in his entirety, God and the world, can only be founded on the
idea and the reality of man's individuality and immortality. For this
fact, the whole book, Insight into Man's Nature, which appeared
in 1811, is an undeniable proof. It is also borne out in the last
chapter of our Anthropology entitled, The Absolute
Personality, which had a wide circulation in the form of a
booklet. We therefore take the liberty to quote from the beginning of
that chapter. The whole inner nature of man has been constructed
on divine misproportions, which are dissolved in the glory of a
super-terrestrial destination, as all motivating springs have their
origin in the spirit and only the weights are from the world. We have
now traced these misproportions with their manifestations from their
dark earthly root, and have followed the spiral of the heavenly plant,
which appears to wind only around a great and noble stem from all
sides and in all directions. We approach the top, which continues to
rise, unattainable and continuously beyond our grasp, into the upper,
brighter realms of another world whose light is only softly dawning on
us and the breath of which we may feel . . .
Such words sound to a man of the present sentimental and not very
scientific, but one only needs to observe the goal toward which
Troxler steers. He does not want to dissolve the nature of man into a
world of ideas but attempts to lay hold on man in man as the
individual and immortal personality. Troxler wants to see the
nature of man anchored in a world that is not merely thought. For this
reason, he calls attention to the fact that one can distinguish
something in the human being that binds man to a world beyond the
sensual world and that is not merely thought.
Philosophers of earlier times have already distinguished a subtle,
noble soul body from the coarser material body, or, in this sense,
assumed a kind of sheath of the spirit, a soul that was endowed with
the picture of the body they called model (Schema) and that was
the inner higher man for them.
Troxler, himself, divided man into material body (Koerper),
soul body (Leib), soul (Seele) and spirit
(Geist). He thereby distinguished the entity of the soul in a
manner that allowed him to see the latter enter the sense world with
its material body and soul body, and extend into a supersensible world
with its soul and spirit. This entity spreads its individual activity
not merely into the sense world but also into the spiritual world. It
does not lose its individuality in the mere generality of thought, but
Troxler does not arrive at the point of conceiving thought as a living
seed of knowledge in the soul. He does not succeed in justifying the
individual members of soul and spirit by letting this germ of
knowledge live within the soul. He does not suspect that thought could
grow into something during his life that could be considered as the
individual life of the soul, but he can speak of this individual
existence of the soul only from a dimly experienced feeling, as it
were. Troxler could not come to more than such a feeling concerning
these connections because he was too dependent on positive dogmatic
religious conceptions. Since he was in possession of a far-reaching
comprehensive knowledge of the evolution of world conception, his
rejection of Hegelian philosophy can nevertheless be seen as of
greater significance than one that springs from mere personal
antipathy. It can be seen as an expression of the objection against
Hegel that arises from the intellectual mood of the Hegelian age
itself. In this light we have to understand Troxler's verdict:
Hegel has brought speculation to the highest stage of its perfection
and in the very act of doing so he has destroyed it. His system has
become for this intellectual current the last word; its indirect
verdict is: Up to this point and not a step further!
In this form Troxler asks the question, which, if developed from a dim
feeling into a clear idea, would probably have to be expressed as
follows: How does the philosophical world conception develop beyond
the phase of the mere thought experience in Hegel's sense to an inner
participation in thought that has come to life?
A book that is characteristic of the relation of Hegel's world
conception toward the mood of the time was published by C. H.
Weisse in 1834 with the title, The Philosophical Secret
Doctrine of the Immortality of the Human Individual. In this book
is to be found the following passage:
Whoever has studied Hegel's philosophy in its entire inner connection,
is acquainted with the manner in which this philosophy, as it is
constructed with perfect consistency in its dialectic method, shows
the subjective spirit of the finite individual as absorbed into
the objective spirit of law, state and morality. The subjective spirit
thus becomes subordinated. It is simultaneously accepted and rejected
until it finally changes into a dependent element of this higher
spirit. In this fashion, the finite individual, as it has long been
noted both in and outside Hegel's school, is made into a transitory
phenomenon. . . . What purpose, what significance could there be for
the continued existence of such an individual after the world spirit
has passed through it . . .?
Weisse attempts to contrast this meaninglessness of the individual
soul with his own description of its imperishable existence. That he,
too, could not really progress beyond Hegel can be easily understood
from his line of thought that has been briefly outlined in an earlier
chapter of this book.
The powerlessness of Hegel's thought picture could be felt when it was
confronted with the individual entity of the soul, and it showed up
again in the rising demand to penetrate deeper into nature than is
possible by mere sense perception. That everything presented to the
senses in reality represents thought and as such is spirit was
seen clearly by Hegel, but whether one had gained an insight into
all spirit in nature by knowing this spirit of nature
as a new question. If the soul cannot grasp its own being by
means of thought, could it not still be the case that with another
form of experience of its own being the soul could nevertheless
experience deeper forces and entities in nature? Whether such
questions are formulated in completely distinct awareness or not is
not the point in question. What matters is whether or not they can
be asked with regard to a world conception. If this is possible,
then such a world conception leaves us with the impression of being
unsatisfactory. Because this was the case with Hegel's philosophy, it
was not accepted as one that gives the right picture of the world,
that is, one to which the highest problems and world riddles could be
referred. This must be distinctly observed if the picture that is
presented by the development of world conception in the middle of the
nineteenth century is to be seen in its proper light. In this time
further progress was made with respect to the picture of external
nature, which, even more powerfully than before, weighed on the
general human outlook on the world. It should be understandable that
the philosophical conceptions of this time were engaged in a hard
struggle since they had, as described above, arrived at a critical
point. To begin with it is noteworthy to observe how Hegel's followers
attempted to defend his philosophy.
Carl Ludwig Michelet (1801 93), the editor of Hegel's
Philosophy of Nature, wrote in his preface to this work in 1841:
Will people continue to consider it a limitation of philosophy to
create only thoughts and not even a leaf of grass? That is to say that
it can create only the general, lasting, truly valuable, and not the
particular, sensual transitory? But if one should see the limitation
of philosophy not only in the fact that philosophy cannot produce the
particular, but also in the fact that it does not even know how
it is made, then the answer is: This how does not
stand higher than knowledge but rather lower than knowledge;
therefore, knowledge cannot have its limitation in this respect. As
the question is asked how this change of the idea into the
reality takes place, knowledge is lost for the reason that nature is
the unconscious idea and the leaf of grass grows without any
knowledge. But true creation of general values is the one element of
which philosophical inquiry cannot be deprived. . . . And now we
maintain that the purest thought development of speculation will be in
the most perfect agreement with the results of experience, and its
sense for nature will discover nothing in nature but embodied ideas.
In the same preface Michelet also expresses a hope:
Thus Goethe and Hegel are the two geniuses who, in my opinion, are
destined to blaze the trail for a speculative physics of the future,
as they prepare the reconciliation of speculation and experience
… . Especially these Hegelian lectures could best of all have
the effect of paving the way for a recognition in this respect, for as
they show a comprehensive empirical knowledge, they represent the
surest test for Hegel's speculation.
The subsequent time did not lead to such a reconciliation. A certain
animosity against Hegel took possession of ever widening circles. The
spread of this feeling against him in the course of the fifties of the
last century can be seen from the words that Friedrich Albert Lange
uses in his History of Materialism in 1865:
His (Hegel's) whole system moves within the realm of our thoughts and
fantasies about things that are given high-sounding names with
complete disregard as to the validity that the phenomena and the
concepts derived from them can have. . . . Through Schelling and
Hegel, pantheism became the dominant mode of thinking in natural
philosophy, a world conception that with a certain mystical depth
implies at the same time, almost as a matter of principle, the danger
of fantastic extravagance. Instead of separating experience and the
world of the senses strictly from the ideal element, and instead of
trying to find the reconciliation of these realms in the nature of
man, the pantheist undertakes the unification of spirit and nature
through the verdict of poetic reason without any critical
intervention.
This view concerning Hegel's mode of thinking is, to be sure, as
inadequate to Hegel's world conception as possible. (See Hegel's
philosophy as described in the chapter, The Classics of World
Conception.) It does dominate numerous spirits as early as the
middle of the nineteenth century, however, and it gains progressively
more ground. A man who, from 1833 to 1872, was in an influential
position with the German intellectual life as a professor of
philosophy in Berlin, Friedrich Adolf Trendelenburg (1802
72), could be sure of meeting strong public approval when he
pronounced the judgment that Hegel wanted to teach without
learning through his method because he was under the impression
that he was in possession of the divine concept, which is
hampered by the process of laborious research work. It was in
vain that Michelet attempted to correct such a judgment by quoting
Hegel's own words: To experience we owe the development of
philosophy. The empirical sciences prepare the content of the
particular to the point where they can be admitted into the realm of
philosophy. They also imply thereby the need of thinking itself to
come up with concrete definitions.
Characteristic of the course of development of the world conceptions
of the middle decades of the nineteenth century is an observation made
by an important but unfortunately little known thinker, K. Ch.
Planck. In the preface of an excellent book published in 1850 and
entitled, The World Ages, he says:
To realize consciously that everything is under the condition of a
purely natural order of law, and at the same time to produce the full
self-conscious freedom of the spirit, the self-dependent inner law of
its nature, this twofold tendency, which is the distinguishing
fundamental signature of modern history, presents in its most direct
and pure form also the task of the present book. The first tendency
becomes apparent on all sides since the revival of the sciences in the
rebirth of independent and comprehensive natural research and its
liberation from the purely religious life. It can be seen in the
change of the whole physical world conception caused by this, as well
as in the ever increasing matter of factness of the view of things in
general. It appears finally, in its highest form, in the philosophical
tendency to comprehend the laws of nature according to their inner
necessity, but it also shows its practical aspect in the gradual
development of this immediate present life with respect to its natural
conditions.
The growing influence of the natural sciences is expressed in words
like this. The confidence in these sciences was becoming greater. The
belief became predominant that through the means and the results of
the natural sciences one could obtain a world conception that is free
from the unsatisfactory elements of the Hegelian one.
A picture of the total change that took place in this direction can be
derived from a book that can be considered as representative of this
period in the fullest sense of the word, Alexander von Humboldt's,
Cosmos, Sketch of a Physical World Description. The author, who
represents the pinnacle of education in the field of physical science
of his time, speaks of his confidence in a world conception of natural
science:
My confidence is based on the splendid state 'of the natural sciences
themselves, whose wealth consists no longer in the abundance of their
facts but in the interconnections of the observations. The general
results that impress every educated mind as interesting have
wonderfully multiplied since the end of the eighteenth century. The
individual facts stand less isolated by themselves; the gaps between
the formations are closed. What remained for a long time obscure to
the inquiring mind when seen in a narrower horizon becomes explained
through the observations that have been obtained on an expedition into
the most distant regions. Forms of plants and animals, which seemed to
be isolated for a long time, are now falling in line through the
discovery of connecting links or through forms of transition. A
general interconnection, not in a simple linear direction, but in a
netlike, woven texture according to a higher development, or the
stunted growth of certain organisms, is what gradually unfolds before
the eye of the inquiring natural observer. . . . The general study of
nature awakens in us, as it were, organs that have long been dormant.
We enter into a more intimate relation with the outer world.
In his Cosmos, Humboldt leads the description of nature only to
the gateway of a world conception. He does not make the attempt to
connect the wealth of the phenomena by means of general ideas of
nature, but links the things and facts in a natural way to each other
as can be expected from the entirely objective turn of his
mind.
Soon other thinkers emerged who were bold enough to make combinations
and who tried to penetrate into the nature of things on the basis of
natural science. What they intended to produce was nothing less than a
radical transformation of all former philosophical world and life
conceptions by means of modern science and knowledge of nature. In the
most forceful way the natural science of the nineteenth century had
paved the way for them. What they intended to do is radically
expressed by Feuerbach:
To assume God before nature is about the same as to assume the church
before you have the stone out of which it is built, or to assume that
the art of architecture has put the stones together to make a building
before the chemical compounds that make up the stone, in short, before
the natural genesis and formation of the stone.
The first half of the century produced many results of natural science
that are bricks for the architecture of a new structure of world
conception. It is, to be sure, correct that a building cannot be
erected if there are no bricks to do it with, but it is no less true
that one cannot do anything with these bricks if, independent of
them, a picture of the building to be erected does not exist. Just
as no structure can come into existence if one puts these bricks
together at random, one upon the other and side by side, joining them
with mortar as they come, so can no world conception come from the
individual known truths of natural science if there is not,
independent of these and of physical research, a power in the
human soul to form the world conception. This fact was left out of
consideration by the antagonists of an independent philosophy.
In examining the personalities who in the eighteen-fifties took part
in the erection of a structure of world conception, the features of
three men are particularly prominent: Ludwig Buechner (1824
99), Carl Vogt (1817 95) and Jacob Moleschott (1822
93). If one wants to characterize the fundamental feeling that
inspires these three men, one need only repeat Moleschott's words:
If man has investigated all properties of the materials that make an
impression on his developed sense organs, he has thereby grasped the
essence of things. With this accomplishment he arrives at his that
is to say, humanity's absolute knowledge. Another knowledge does not
exist for man.
All philosophy that has been so far advanced has, according to these
men, yielded only knowledge without lasting meaning. The idealistic
philosophers believe, according to Buechner and those who shared his
views, that they derive their knowledge from reason. Through this
method, however, one cannot, as Buechner maintains, come to a
meaningful structure of conceptions. But truth can only be
gained by listening to nature and her rule, says Moleschott. At
that time and during the following years, the protagonists for such a
world conception, directly derived from nature, were collectively
called materialists. It was emphatically declared that this
materialism was an age-old world conception, concerning which
enlightened spirits had long recognized how unsatisfactory it was for
a higher thinker. Buechner attacked that opinion. He pointed out that:
In the first place materialism, or the whole philosophical current
moving in its direction, has never been disproved. It is not only the
oldest form of philosophical contemplation in existence but also one
that emerged anew with new energies at every revival of philosophy in
the course of history. Furthermore, the materialism of our day is no
longer the same as it was formerly with Epicurus or the
Encyclopedists, but an entirely different thought current or methods,
which is supported by the results of the positive sciences. This is a
method that is distinguished from its preceding form by the fact that
it is no more like the older materialism, a system, but a simple
realistic philosophical contemplation of existence that, above all,
traces the uniform principle in the world of nature and of the spirit,
striving to show everywhere a natural and law-determined connection of
all phenomena of that world.
Goethe's attitude toward Holbach, one of the most prominent
materialists of the eighteenth century French Encyclopedists,
illustrates the position a spirit, who strives in a most pronounced
way for a thinking in accordance with nature and does full justice to
the mode of conception of natural science, can nevertheless take
toward materialism. Paul Heinrich Dietrich von Holbach (1723
1789) published his Systeme de la Nature in 1770. Goethe, who
came across this book in Strassburg, in Poetry and Truth
describes the repulsive impression that he received from it.
Matter was to be there from eternity, and it was to have been in
motion from eternity. Through this motion, now to the right, now to
the left in all directions, it was to have produced without further
difficulty all the infinite phenomena of existence. This we might even
have accepted as satisfactory if the author had really constructed
before our eyes the world out of his matter in motion. But he might
have known as little about nature as we did, for after postulating a
few general concepts, he again turns away from nature in order to
transform what appears higher than nature, or what appears as a higher
nature in nature, into the material, heavy nature, to be sure, in
motion, but without direction and shape, and he thinks that he gained
a great deal in so doing.
Goethe was deeply convinced that theory in itself and by itself
has no value except to make us believe in the connection of the
phenomena. (Sprueche in Prosa, Deutsche
Nationalliteratur, Goethe's Werke, Vol. 36, 2, pp. 357.)
The results of natural science gained in the first half of the
nineteenth century were, to be sure, as knowledge of facts,
well-suited to supply a foundation to the materialists of the fifties
for their world conception. Science has penetrated deeper and deeper
into the connections of the material processes insofar as they can be
reached by sense observation and by the form of thinking that is based
on that sense observation. If one now wants to deny to oneself and to
others that there is spirit active in matter, one nevertheless
unconsciously reveals this spirit. For what Friedrich Theodor Vischer
says in the third volume of his essay, On Old and New Things,
is in a certain sense quite correct. That the so-called
matter can produce something, the function of which is spirit, is in
itself the complete proof against materialism. In this sense,
Buechner unconsciously disproves materialism by attempting to prove
that the spiritual processes spring from the depths of the material
facts presented to sense observation.
An example that shows how the results of natural science took on forms
that could be of a deeply penetrating influence on the conception of
the world is given in Woehler's discovery of 1828. This
scientist succeeded in producing a substance synthetically outside the
living organism that had previously only been known to be formed
within. This experiment seemed to supply the proof that the former
belief, which assumed that certain material compounds could be formed
only under the influence of a special life force contained in the
organism, was incorrect. If it was possible to produce such compounds
outside the living body, then one could draw the conclusion that the
organism was also working only with the forces with which chemistry
deals. The thought arose for the materialists that, if the living
organism does not need a special life force to produce what formerly
had been attributed to such a force, why should this organism then
need special spiritual energies in order to produce the processes to
which mental experiences are bound? Matter in all its qualities now
became for the materialists what generates all things and processes
from its core. From the fact that carbon, hydrogen, oxygen and
nitrogen combine in an organic compound, it did not seem far to go to
Buechner's statement, The words soul, spirit, thought, feeling,
will, life, do not stand for any real things but only for properties,
qualifications, functions of the living substance, or results of
entities that have their basis in the material forms of
existence. A divine being or the human soul were no longer
called immortal by Buechner, but rather matter and energy. Moleschott
expressed the same conviction with the words:
Energy is not a creative God; no essence of things is detachable from
the material basis. It is a quality of matter, inseparable from it,
eternally inherent in it. Carbon, hydrogen and oxygen are the powers
that split the firmest rock and transform it into fluid processes in
which life is generated. Change of matter and form in the individual
parts while the fundamental structure remains the same is the mystery
of animal life.
The research done in the first half of the nineteenth century in
natural science enabled Ludwig Buechner to express the view, "In
a way similar to that in which the steam engine produces motion, the
intricate organic complication of energy endowed materials in the
animal body produces a sum total of certain effects, which, combined
in a unity, are called spirit, soul, thought by us. And Karl
Gustav Reuschle declared in his book, Philosophy and Natural
Science, in Memory of David Friedrich Strauss (1874), that the
results of natural science themselves implied a philosophical element.
The affinities that one discovered between the natural forces were
thought to lead into the mysteries of existence.
Such an important relation was found by Oersted in 1819 in
Copenhagen. He saw that a magnetic needle is deflected by an electric
current. Faraday discovered the corresponding phenomenon in
1831, that by moving a magnet toward a spirally twisted copper wire,
electricity can be generated in the latter. Electricity and magnetism
thereby were shown to be related natural phenomena. Both energies were
no longer isolated facts; it was now apparent that they had a common
basis in their material existence. Julius Robert Mayer
penetrated deeper into the nature of matter and energy in the
eighteen-forties when he became aware of the fact that there exists a
definite relation that can be expressed numerically between mechanical
work and heat. Out of pressure, impact and friction, etc., that is to
say, out of work, heat is generated. In the steam engine, heat is
again changed into work. The quantity of heat produced by a given
amount of work can be calculated from the quantity of this work. If
one changes the quantity of heat that is necessary to heat a kilogram
of water by one degree centigrade into work, one can with this work
lift 424 kilograms to a height of one meter. It cannot be surprising
that the discovery of such facts was considered to be a vast progress
away from such explanations concerning matter as Hegel had offered:
The transition from ideality to reality, from abstraction to
concrete existence, in this case, from space and time to the reality
that appears as matter, is incomprehensible for the intellect and
therefore appears to it always as something external and merely
given. The significance of a remark of this kind is recognized
only if thought as such can be seen as something valuable. This
consideration, however, would not occur to the above-mentioned
thinkers.
To discoveries such as these concerning the unity of the organic
forces of nature, others were added that threw light on the problem of
the composition of the world of organisms. In 1838 the botanist,
Schleiden, recognized the significance of the simple cell for
the plant organism. He showed that every texture of the plant, and
therefore the plant itself, is made up of these elementary
organisms. Schleiden had recognized this elementary
organism as a little drop of mucilaginous fluid surrounded by a
cellular membrane. These cells are so multiplied and joined to one
another that they form the structure of the plant. Soon after this,
Schwann discovered the same general structure for the world of
animal organisms. Then, in 1827, the brilliant naturalist, Karl
Ernst van Baer, discovered the human egg. He also described the
process of the development of higher animals and of man from the egg.
In this way one had everywhere given up the attempt to look for ideas
that could be considered fundamental for the things of nature.
Instead, one had observed the facts that show in which way the higher,
more complicated processes and entities of nature develop from the
simpler and lower ones. The men who were in search of an idealistic
interpretation of the phenomena of the world became ever more rare. It
was still the spirit of idealistic world conception that in 1837
inspired the anthropologist, Burdach, with the view that life did not
have its origin in matter but rather a higher force transformed matter
according to its own design. Moleschott had already said, The
force of life, as life itself, is nothing more than the result of the
complicated interacting and interweaving physical and chemical
forces.
The consciousness of the time tended to explain the universe through
no other phenomena than those that are displayed before the eyes of
men. Charles Lyell's work, Principles of Geology, which was
published in 1830, brought the whole older geology to an end with this
principle of explanation. Up to Lyell's epoch-making work it was
believed that the evolution of the earth had taken place in abrupt
revolutions. Everything that had come into being on earth was supposed
to have been destroyed repeatedly by complete catastrophes. Over the
graves of the victims new creations were supposed to have risen. In
this manner, one explained the presence of the remnants of plants and
animals in the various strata of the earth. Cuvier was the principal
representative who believed in such repeated periods of creation.
Lyell was convinced that it was unnecessary to assume such
interruptions of the steady course of evolution of the earth. If one
only presupposed sufficiently long periods of time, one could say that
forces today still at work on earth caused the entire development. In
Germany, Goethe and Karl von Hoff had already professed such a view.
Von Hoff maintained it in his History of the Natural Changes of the
Surface of the Earth, Documented by Traditional Sources, which
appeared in 1822. With great boldness of thought, enthusiasts Vogt,
Buechner and Moleschott set out to explain all phenomena from material
processes as they take place before the senses of man.
The situation that arose when the physiologist, Rudolf Wagner, found
himself opposed by Carl Vogt was typical of the intellectual warfare
that the materialists had to wage. In 1852, in the paper,
Allgemeine Zeitung, Wagner had declared himself in favor of
accepting an independent soul entity, thereby opposing the view of
materialism. He said that the soul could divide itself because
the child inherited much from his father and much also from his
mother. Vogt answered this statement for the first time in his
Pictures from Animal Life. His position in this controversy is
clearly exposed in the following:
The soul, which is to be the substance, the very essence of the
individuality of the individual, indivisible entity, is to be capable
of dividing itself. Theologists, be sure you catch this heretic. He
has been up to now one of your people! Divided souls! If the soul can
be divided in the act of conception as Mr. Rudolf Wagner thinks, then
it could also be possible that this soul could be divided in death,
the portion that was burdened with sins going into purgatory, while
the other part would go directly into paradise. Mr. Wagner also
promises at the end of his physiological letters some excursions into
the field of the physiology of the divided souls.
The controversy became intense when Wagner, at the assembly of natural
scientists in Goettingen in 1854, read a paper against materialism
entitled, Man's Creation and the Substance of the Soul. He
meant to prove two things. In the first place, he set out to show that
the results of modern physical science were not a contradiction of the
biblical belief in the descent of the human race from one couple. In
the second instance, he wanted to demonstrate that these results did
not imply anything concerning the soul. Vogt wrote a polemical
treatise, Bigoted Faith and Science (Koehlerglaube und
Wissenschaft), against Wagner in 1855, which showed him to be
equipped with the full insight of the natural science of his time. At
the same time, he appeared to be a sharp thinker who, without reserve,
disclosed his opponents' conclusions as illusions. Vogt's
contradiction of Wagner's first statement comes to a climax in the
passage, All investigations of history and of natural history
lead to the positive proof of the origin of the human races from a
plurality of roots. The doctrines of the Scripture concerning Adam and
Noah, and the twice occurring descent of man from a single couple are
scientifically untenable legends.
Against Wagner's doctrine of the soul, Vogt maintained that we see the
psychical activities of man develop gradually as part of the
development of the physical organs. From childhood to the maturity of
life we observe that the spiritual activities become more perfect.
With the shrinking of the senses and the brain, the spirit
shrinks proportionally. A development of this kind is not
consistent with the assumption of an immortal soul substance that has
been planted into the brain as its organ.
That the materialists, as they fought their opponents, were not merely
confronted with intellectual reasons but also with emotions, becomes
perfectly clear in the controversy between Vogt and Wagner. For Wagner
had appealed, in a paper at Goettingen, for the moral need that could
not endure the thought that mechanical machines walking about
with two arms and legs should finally be dissolved into
indifferent material substances, without leaving us the hope that the
good they are doing should be rewarded and the evil punished. Vogt's
answer was, The existence of an immortal soul is, for Mr.
Wagner, not the result of investigation and thought. . . . He needs an
immortal soul in order to see it tortured and punished after the death
of man.
Heinrich Czolbe (1819 73) attempted to show that there
is a point of view from which the moral world order can be in agreement
with the views of materialism. In his book, The Limits and Origin
of Knowledge Seen in Opposition to Kant and Hegel, which appeared
in 1865, he explained that every theology had its origin in a
dissatisfaction with this world.
The exclusion of the supersensible, or those incomprehensible things
that lead to the assumption of a second world, that is, to naturalism,
is in no way forced upon us through the power of the facts of natural
science not even through philosophy that means to know everything
but in the last analysis through morality, namely, through that
particular kind of moral behavior in man toward the world that we can
call satisfaction with the natural world.
Czolbe considers the longing for a supernatural world actually a.
result of an ingratitude against the natural world. The basic causes
of a philosophy that looks toward a world beyond this one are, for
him, moral shortcomings, sins against the spirit of the natural world
order. For these sins distract us from the striving toward the
highest possible happiness of every individual and from
fulfilling the duty that follows from such a striving against
ourselves and others without regard for supernatural reward and
punishment. According to Czolbe, every human being is to be
filled with a grateful acceptance of his share of earthly
happiness, which may be possibly small, and with a humble acceptance
of its limits and its necessary sorrow. Here we meet a rejection
of a supernatural world order for moral reasons.
In Czolbe's world conception one also sees clearly what qualities made
materialism so acceptable to human thinking, for there is no doubt
that Buechner, Vogt and Moleschott were not philosophers to a
sufficient degree to demonstrate the foundations of their views
logically. Without losing their way in heights of idealistic thoughts,
in their capacity as naturalists they drew their conclusions more from
sense observations. To render an account of their method by justifying
it from the nature of human knowledge was no enterprise to their
liking. Czolbe, however, did undertake just that. In his New
Presentation of Sensualism (1855), we find the reasons given why
he considers a knowledge built on the basis of sensual perceptions
valuable. Only a knowledge of this kind supplies concepts, judgments
and conclusions that can be distinctly conceived and envisaged. Every
conclusion that leads to something sensually inconceivable, and every
indistinct concept is to be rejected. The soul element is not clearly
conceivable, according to Czolbe, but the material on which the
spiritual appears as a quality. He therefore attempts to reduce
self-consciousness to visible material processes in the essay he
published in 1856, The Genesis of Self-consciousness, an Answer to
Professor Lotze. Here he assumes a circular movement of the parts
of the brain. Through such a motion returning in its own track, the
impression that a thing causes in the senses is made into a conscious
sensation. It is strange that this physical explanation of
consciousness became, at the same time, the occasion for him to
abandon his materialism. This is the point where one of the weaknesses
inherent in materialism becomes apparent in him. If he had remained
faithful to his principle, he would never have gone further than the
facts that are accessible to the senses allow. He would speak of no
other processes in the brain than those that can positively be
asserted through the means of natural science. What Czolbe sets out to
establish is, however, an aim in an infinite distance. Spirits like
Czolbe are not satisfied with what is investigated, they
hypothetically assume facts that have not as yet been investigated.
Such an alleged fact is the circular motion of the parts of the brain.
A complete investigation of the brain will most likely lead to the
discovery of processes of a kind that do not occur anywhere else in
the world. From them, one will be able to draw the conclusion that the
psychical processes conditioned by brain processes do occur only
in connection with a brain. Concerning his hypothetical circular
movements, Czolbe could not claim that they were limited to the brain.
They could occur also outside the animal organism, but in that case,
they would have to lead to psychical phenomena also in inanimate
objects. Czolbe, who is so insistent on perceptual clarity, actually
does not consider an animation of all nature as impossible. He asks,
Should not my view be a realization of the world soul, which
Plato defended in his Timaeus? Should we not be able to find here the
point where the Leibnizian idealism, which has the whole world consist
of animated entities (monads), unites with modern naturalism?
On a larger scale the mistake that Czolbe made with circular brain
motion occurred again in the brilliant thinker, Carl Christian
Planck (1819 80). The writings of this man have been completely
forgotten, in spite of the fact that they belong to the most
interesting works of modern philosophy. Planck strives as intensely as
any materialist for a world conception that is completely derived from
perceptible reality. He criticizes the German idealism of Fichte,
Schelling and Hegel for seeking the essence of things one-sidedly in
the idea. To explain things really out of themselves is to
recognize them in their original conditioned state and in their
finiteness. (Compare Planck, The World Ages.) There
is only the one and truly pure nature, so that mere nature in the
narrower sense of the word and spirit are opposites only within the
one nature in the higher and more comprehensive sense.
Now the strange thing happens in Planck's philosophy that he declares
the real, the world extending before him, to be the element that the
explanation of the world has to seek. He nevertheless does not proceed
with the observation of the facts in order to reach this element of
the real world extending before him, for he believes that human reason
is capable of penetrating through its own power to the real. Hegel
had, according to Planck, made the mistake of having reason
contemplate its own being so that it saw itself again in all things.
Planck, however, intended to have reason no longer withheld within its
own limits, but to have it go beyond itself into the element of
extension, the truly real. Planck blames Hegel because Hegel had
reason spin its own cobweb out of itself, whereas he, himself, is bold
enough to have reason spin real objective existence. Hegel maintained
that the spirit is capable of comprehending the essence of things
because reason is the essence of things and because it comes
into being in the human spirit. Planck declares that the essence of
things is not reason, but he uses reason merely to represent this
essence. A bold world construction, brilliantly conceived, but
conceived far from real observation, far from real things, yet
constructed in the belief that it was entirely permeated with genuine
reality such is Planck's structure of ideas. He considers the world
process a living interplay of expansion and contraction. Gravity is
for him the tendency of the bodies, spread in space, to contract. Heat
and light are the tendency of a body to bring its contracted matter
into activity at a distance, and therefore the tendency of expansion.
Planck's relation toward his contemporaries is most interesting.
Feuerbach said of himself, Hegel maintains the standpoint that
he wants to construct the world; my standpoint is to know the world as
being; he descends, I ascend. Hegel stands man on his head; I place
him on his feet, which are resting on geology. With these words
the materialists could also have characterized their credo, but Planck
proceeds in his method exactly like Hegel. He believes, however, that
he proceeds like Feuerbach and the materialists. The materialists, if
they had interpreted his method in their own way, would have had to
say to him, From your standpoint you attempt to construct the
world. Nevertheless, you believe you proceed by recognizing the world
as being; you descend, but you take this descent to be an ascent. You
stand the world on its head and you are of the opinion that that head
is a foot. The will toward natural, factual reality could
probably not be expressed more poignantly than through the world
conception of a man who wanted to produce not merely ideas but reality
out of reason.
The personality of Planck appears no less interesting when he is
compared with his contemporary, Max Stirner. It is significant here to
consider Planck's ideas concerning the motivations of human action and
community life. As the materialist proceeded from the materials and
forces actually presented to the senses to arrive at their explanation
of nature, so Stirner started from the real individual personality as
a guide line for human behavior. Reason is only with the individual.
What reason decides on as a guide line for action can therefore also
have validity only for the individual. Life in community will
naturally result from the natural interaction of the individual
personalities. If everyone acts according to his reason, the most
desirable state of affairs will come to pass through the most free
cooperation of all. The natural community life comes into being as a
matter of course if everyone has reason rule his own individuality
since, according to the materialists, the natural view of worldly
phenomena comes to pass if one has the things express their nature and
if one limits the activity of reason to a mere combination and
interpretation of the statements of the senses. As Planck does not
explain the world by allowing things to speak for themselves, but
decides by his reason what the things allegedly say, so he also does
not, in regard to community life, depend on a real interaction of
personalities but dreams of an association of peoples with a supreme
judicial power serving the general welfare and ordered by reason. Here
also, then, he considers it possible that reason should master what
lies beyond the personality.
The original general law of right demands necessarily its external
existence in a general power of right, for it would itself not be real
as a general element in an external form if it were left to the
individuals themselves to execute it, as the individuals by themselves
are, according to their legal positions, only representatives of their
personal right, not as the general right as such.
Planck constructs the general power of right because he can realize
the idea of right for himself only in this manner. Five years earlier,
Max Stirner had written, My own master and the creator of my own
right I recognize no other source of right than myself. Neither God,
nor state, nor nature, nor man himself with his eternal human
rights, neither a divine nor a human right. It is his opinion
that the real right of the individual cannot exist within a general
right. It is thirst for reality that drives Stirner to take his
negative attitude toward an unreal general right. It is the same
thirst for reality that, in turn, motivates Planck in his attempt to
crystallize out of an idea a real state of right.
In reading Planck's books one feels that he was deeply disturbed by
the thought of a twofold world order. He considered the belief in such
an interaction of two world orders a natural order and a purely
spiritual one as something contrary to nature and intolerable.
There have been thinkers before Planck's time, of course, who strove
for a purely natural-scientific mode of conception. Leaving aside
several other more or less clear attempts in this direction, Lamarck,
for instance, in 1809 outlined a picture of the genesis and
development of living organisms, which, according to the state of
knowledge of his time, should have had a great deal of attraction for
a contemporary world conception. He thought of the simplest organisms
as having come into existence through inorganic processes under
certain conditions. Once an organism is formed in this way, it
develops, through adjustment to given conditions of the external
world, new formations that serve its life. It grows new organs because
it needs them. The organisms then are capable of transformation and
thereby also of perfection. Lamarck imagines this transformation in
the following way. Consider an animal that gets its food from high
trees. It is therefore compelled to stretch its neck. In the course of
time its neck then becomes longer under the influence of this need. A
short-necked animal is transformed into the giraffe with its long
neck. The animals, then, have not come into existence in their
variety, but this variety has developed in the course of time under
the influence of changing conditions. Lamarck is of the opinion that
man is included in this evolution. Man has developed in the course of
time out of related forms similar to monkeys into forms that allowed
him to satisfy higher physical and spiritual needs. Lamarck in this
way linked up the whole world of organisms, including man, to the
realm of the inorganic.
Lamarck's attempt at an explanation of the varieties of the forms of
life was met with little attention by his contemporaries. Two decades
later a controversy arose in the French Academy between Geoffroy St.
Hilaire and George Cuvier. Geoffroy St. Hilaire believed he recognized
a common structural design in the world of animal organisms in spite
of its great variety. Such a general plan was a necessary prerequisite
for an explanation of their development from one another. If they had
developed from one another, they must have had some fundamental common
element in spite of their variety. In the lowest animal something must
be recognizable that only needs perfection in order to change this
lower form in the course of time into that of a higher animal. Cuvier
turned strongly against the consequences of this view. He was a
cautious man who pointed out that the facts did not uphold such
far-reaching conclusions. As soon as Goethe heard of this conflict, he
considered it the most important event of the time. Compared to this
controversy, the interest that he took in the July Revolution, a
political event that took place at the same time, appears
insignificant … . Goethe expressed himself on this point
clearly enough in a conversation that he had with Soret in August,
1830. He saw clearly that the adequate conception of the organic world
depended on this controversial point. In an essay Goethe supported St.
Hilaire with great intensity. (Compare Goethe's writings on natural
science, Vol. 36, Goethe Edition, Deutsche National Literatur.) He
told Johannes von Mueller that he considered Geoffroy St. Hilaire to
be moving in the same direction he himself had taken up fifty years
earlier. This shows clearly what Goethe meant to do when he began,
shortly after his arrival in Weimar, to take up his studies on animal
and plant formations. Even then he had an explanation of the variety
of living forms in mind that was more adequate to nature, but he was
also a cautious man. He never maintained more than what the facts
entitled him to state, and he tells in his introduction to his
Metamorphosis of the Plant that the time was then in
considerable confusion with respect to these facts. The opinion
prevailed, as Goethe expressed it, that it was only necessary for the
monkey to stand up and to walk on his hind legs in order to become a
human being.
The thinkers of natural science maintained a mode of conception that
was completely different from that of the Hegelians. For the
Hegelians, it was possible to remain within their ideal world. They
could develop their idea of man from their idea of the monkey without
being concerned with the question of how nature could manage to bring
man into being in the real world side by side with the monkey.
Michelet had simply pronounced that it was no concern of the idea to
explain the specific how of the processes in the real
world. The thinker who forms an idealistic world conception is, in
this respect, in the same position as the mathematician who only has
to say through what thought operation a circle is changed into an
ellipse and an ellipse into a parabola or hyperbola. A thinker,
however, who strives for an explanation through facts would have to
point at the actual processes through which such a transformation can
come to pass. He is then forming a realistic world conception. Such a
thinker will not take the position that Hegel describes:
It has been a clumsy conception of the older and also of the more
recent philosophy of nature to consider the development and transition
of one form and realm of nature into a higher one as an external and
real production that one has dated back into the darkness of the past
for the sake of clarification. It is characteristic of nature to be so
external in its structure that its forms fall apart in differentiated
manifestations and that these. forms exist indifferently side by side;
the idea, which guides the stages in their succession, is the
inner nature of these separated manifestations. Such nebulous
conceptions, which are really just sensual conceptions, as, for
instance, the alleged progression of plants and animals from water,
and then again, the evolution of the more developed animal formations
from the lower ones, and so forth, must be given up by a thoughtful
contemplation. (Hegel's Werke, 1847, Vol. 7, p. 33.)
In opposition to such a statement of an idealistic thinker, we hear
that of the realistic Lamarck:
In the primal beginning only the simplest and lowest animals and
plants developed, and only lastly those of a highly complicated
organization. The course of the evolution of the earth and its organic
population was quite gradual and not interrupted by violent
revolutions. The simplest animals and the simplest plants that occupy
the lowest stages on the scale of organisms have come into existence,
and do so even today, through spontaneous generation (generatio
spontanea).
There was in Germany also a man of the same conviction as Lamarck.
Lorenz Oken (1779 1859) presented a natural evolution of
organic beings that was based on sensual conceptions. To
quote him, Everything organic has originated from a slimy
substance (Urschleim), is merely slime formed in various ways.
This original slime has come into being in the ocean in the course of
the planetary evolution out of inorganic matter.
In spite of such deeply provocative turns of thought there had to be,
especially with thinkers who were too cautious to leave the thread of
factual knowledge, a doubt against a naturalistic mode of thinking of
this kind as long as the question of the teleology of living beings
had not been cleared. Even Johannes Mueller, who was a pioneer as a
thinker and as a research scientist, was, because of his consideration
of the idea of teleology, prompted to say:
The organic bodies are distinguished from the inorganic not merely by
the composition of elements that they represent, but also by the
continuous activity that is at work in living organic matter, which
creates also teleologically and in a reason-directed plan, by
arranging the parts for the purpose of the whole. It is this that is
the distinguishing mark of an organism. (Johannes Mueller, Handbuch
der Physiologic des Menschen, 3, 1838; Vol. 1, p. 19.)
With a man like Johannes Mueller, who remained strictly within the
limits of natural scientific research, and for whom the thought of
purpose-conformity remained as a private conviction in the background
of his factual research work, this view was not likely to produce any
particular consequences. He investigated the laws of the organisms in
strict objectivity regardless of the purpose connection, and became a
reformer of modern natural science through his comprehensive mind; he
knew how to make use of the physical, chemical, anatomical,
zoological, microscopical and embryological knowledge in an unlimited
way. His view did not keep him from basing psychological qualities of
the objects of his studies on their physical characteristics. It was
one of his fundamental convictions that no one could be a psychologist
without being a physiologist. But if a thinker went beyond the field
of research in natural science and entered the realm of a general
world conception, he was not in the fortunate position easily to
discard an idea like that of teleological structure. For this reason,
it is easy to understand why a thinker of the importance of Gustave
Theodor Fechner (1801 87) would make the statement in his book,
Zend-Avesta, or Concerning the Nature of Heaven and the World
Beyond (1852), that it seems strange how anyone can believe that
no consciousness would be necessary to create conscious beings as the
human beings are, since even unconscious machines can be created only
by conscious human beings. Also, Karl Ernst von Baer, who
followed the evolution of the animals from their initial state, could
not resist the thought that the processes in living organisms were
striving toward certain goals and that the full concept of purpose
was, indeed, to be applied for all of nature. (Karl Ernst von Baer,
Studies from the Field of Natural Science, 1876, pp. 73 &
82.)
Difficulties of this kind, which confront certain thinkers as they
intend to build up a world picture, the elements of which are supposed
to be taken entirely from the sensually perceptible nature, were not
even noticed by materialistic thinkers. They attempted to oppose the
idealistic world picture of the first half of the century with one
that receives a11 explanation exclusively from the facts of nature.
Only in a knowledge that had been gained from these facts did they
have any confidence.
There is nothing more enlightening concerning the inner conviction of
the materialists than this confidence. They have been accused of
taking the soul out of things and thereby depriving them of what
speaks to man's heart, his feelings. Does it not seem that they do
take all qualities out of nature that lift man's spirit and that they
debase nature into a dead object that satisfies only the intellect
that looks for causes but deprives us of any inner involvement? Does
it not seem that they undermine morality that rises above mere natural
appetites and looks for motivations, merely advocating the cause of
animal desires, subscribing to the motto: Let us eat and drink and
follow our physical instincts for tomorrow we die? Lotze (1817 81)
indeed makes the statement with respect to the materialistic thinkers
of the time in question that the followers of this movement value the
truth of the drab empirical knowledge in proportion to the degree in
which it offends everything that man's inner feelings hold sacred.
When one becomes acquainted, however, with Carl Vogt, one finds in him
a man who had a deep understanding for the beauty of nature and who
attempted to express this as an amateur painter. He was a person who
was not at all blind to the creations of human imagination but felt at
home with painters and poets. Quite a number of materialists were
inspired by the esthetic enjoyment of the wonderful structure of
organisms to a point where they felt that the soul must have its
origin in the body. The magnificent structure of the human brain
impressed them much more than the abstract concepts with which
philosophy was concerned. How much more claim to be considered as the
causes of the spirit, therefore, did the former seem to present than
the latter.
Nor can the reproach that the materialists debased morality be
accepted without reserve. Their knowledge of nature was deeply bound
up with ethical motivations. Czolbe's endeavor to stress the moral
foundation of naturalism was shared by other materialists. They all
meant to instill in man the joy of natural existence; they intended to
direct him toward his duties and his tasks on earth. They felt that
human dignity could be enhanced if man could be conscious of having
developed from a lower being to his present state of perfection. They
believed that only a man who knows the material necessities that
underlie his actions is capable of properly judging them. They argued
that only he knows how to judge a man according to his value
who is aware that matter is the basis for life in the universe, that
with natural necessity life is connected with thought and thought in
turn gives rise to good and ill will. To those who see moral freedom
endangered by materialism, Moleschott answers:
Everybody is free who is joyfully aware of the natural necessity of
his existence, his circumstances, claims and demands, and of the
limits and extent of his sphere of activity. A man who understands
this natural necessity knows also his right to fight his way through
for demands that are in accordance with the needs of the human race.
More than that, because only that freedom that is in harmony with the
genuinely human will be defended with natural necessity by the
species. We can be assured of the final victory over all suppressors
in any struggle for human ends.
With attitudes of this kind, with a devotion to the wonders of nature,
with moral sentiments as described above, the materialists were ready
to receive the man who overcame the great obstacle for a naturalistic
world conception. This man appeared to them in Charles Darwin.
His work, through which the teleological idea was placed on the
solid ground of natural science, was published in 1859 with the title,
The Origin of the Species by Means of Natural Selection, or the
Preservation of Favored Races in the Struggle for Life.
For an understanding of the impulses that are at work in the evolution
of philosophical world conception, the examples of the advances in
natural science mentioned (to which many others could be added) are
not significant in themselves. What is important is the fact
that advances of this kind coincided in time with the development of
the Hegelian world picture. The presentation of the course of
evolution of philosophy in the previous chapters has shown that the
modern world picture, since the days of Copernicus, Galileo, etc.,
stood under the influence of the mode of conception of natural
science. This influence, however, could not be as significant as that
of the accomplishment of the natural sciences of the nineteenth
century. There were also important advances of natural science at the
turn of the eighteenth to the nineteenth centuries. We only need to be
reminded of the discovery of oxygen by Lavoisier, and of the findings
in the field of electricity by Volta and many others. In spite of
these discoveries spirits like Fichte, Schelling and Goethe could,
while they fully recognized these advances, nevertheless, arrive at a
world picture that started from the spirit. They could not be so
powerfully impressed by the mode of conception of natural science as
were the materialistic thinkers in the middle of the nineteenth
century. It was still possible to recognize on the one side of
the world picture the conceptions of natural science, and on the
other side of it, certain conceptions that contained more
than mere thought. Such a conception was, for
instance, that of the force of life, or of the
teleological structure of an organism. Conceptions of this
kind made it possible to say that there is something at work in the
world that does not come under the ordinary natural law, something
that is more spiritual. In this fashion one obtained a conception of
the spirit that had, as it were, a factual content. Hegel
had then proceeded to deprive the spirit of all factual elements. He
had diluted it into mere thought. For those for whom
mere thoughts could be nothing but pictures of
factual elements, this step appeared as the philosophical proof of the
unreality of the spirit. These thinkers felt that they had to find
something that possessed a real content for them to take the place of
Hegel's mere thought things. For this reason, they sought
the origin of the spiritual phenomena in material
processes that could be sensually observed as facts. The
world conception was pressed toward the thought of the material origin
of the spirit through the transformation of the spirit that Hegel had
brought about.
If one understands that there are deeper forces at work in the
historical course of human evolution than those appearing on the
surface, one will recognize the significance for the development of
world conception that lies in the characteristic attitude that the
materialism of the nineteenth century takes toward the formation of
the Hegelian philosophy. Goethe's thoughts contained the seeds for a
continuation of a philosophy that was taken up by Hegel, but
insufficiently. If Goethe attempted to obtain a conception with his
archetypal plant that allowed him to experience this
thought inwardly so that he could intellectually derive from it such a
specific plant formation as would be capable of life, he showed
thereby that he was striving to bring thought to life within his soul.
Goethe had reached the point where thought was about to begin a
lifelike evolution, while Hegel did not go beyond thought as such. In
communion with a thought that had come to life within the soul, as
Goethe attempted, one would have had a spiritual experience that could
have recognized the spirit also in matter. In mere thought
one had no such experience. Thus, the evolution of world conception
was put to a hard test. According to the deeper historical impulses,
the modern time tended to experience not thought alone, but to
find a conception for the self-conscious ego through which one could
be aware that this ego is firmly rooted in the structure of the world.
In conceiving this ego as a product of material processes, one had
pursued this tendency by simply following the trend in a form easily
understandable at that time. Even the denial of the spiritual
entity of the self-conscious ego by the materialism of the nineteenth
century still contains the impulse of the search for this ego. For
this reason, the impulse with which natural science affected
philosophy in this age was quite different from the influences it had
had on previous materialistic currents. These earlier currents had not
as yet been so hard pressed by something comparable to Hegel's thought
philosophy to seek for a safe ground in the natural sciences. This
pressure, to be sure, does not affect the leading personalities to a
point where they are clearly aware of it, but as an impulse of the
time, it exerts its effect in the subconscious currents of the soul.
|
Last Modified: 17-Jul-2009 |
The Rudolf Steiner Archive is maintained by:
The e.Librarian:
elibrarian@elib.com
|
|
|
|
|