|
The Riddles of Philosophy
Modern Idealistic World Conceptions
In the second half of the nineteenth century, the mode of conception
of natural science was blended with the idealistic traditions from the
first half, producing three world conceptions that show a distinctive
individual physiognomy. The three thinkers responsible for this were
Rudolf Hermann Lotze (1817 81), Gustav Theodor Fechner
(1801 87), and Eduard von Hartmann (1842 1906).
In his work, Life and Life-force, which appeared in 1842 in
Wagner's Handwörterbuch der Physiologic, Lotze opposed the
belief that there is in living beings a special force, the life force,
and defended the thought that the phenomena of life are to be
explained exclusively through complicated processes of the same kind
as take place in lifeless nature. In this respect, he sided entirely
with the mode of conception of modern natural science, which tried to
bridge the gap between the lifeless and the living. This attitude is
reflected in his books that deal with subjects of natural science,
General Pathology and Therapy as Mechanical Sciences (1842) and
General Physiology of the Physical Life (1851). With his
Elements of Psychophysics (1860) and Propaedeutics of
Esthetics (1876), Fechner contributed works that show the spirit
of a strictly natural scientific mode of conception. This was now done
in fields that before him had been treated almost without exception in
the sense of an idealistic mode of thinking. But Lotze and Fechner
felt that need to construct for themselves an idealistic world of
thought that went beyond the view of natural science. Lotze was forced
to take this direction through the quality of his inner disposition.
This demanded of him not merely an intellectual observation of the
natural law in the world, but challenged him to seek life and
inwardness of the kind that man feels within himself in all things and
processes. He wanted to struggle constantly against the
conceptions that acknowledge only one half of the world, and the less
important one at that, only the unfolding of facts into new facts, of
forms into new forms, but not the constant reconversion of all those
externalities into elements of inner relevance, into what alone has
value and truth in the world, into bliss and despair, admiration and
disgust, love and hatred, into joyful certainty and doubtful yearning,
into all the nameless forms of suspense and fear in which life goes
on, that alone deserves to be called life.
Lotze, like many others, has the feeling that the human picture of
nature becomes cold and drab if we do not permeate it with the
conceptions that are taken from the human soul (compare above
pages . . . ) What in Lotze is caused by his inner disposition of feeling,
appears in Fechner as the result of a richly developed imagination
that has the effect of always leading from a logical comprehension of
things to a poetic interpretation of them. He cannot, as a natural
scientific thinker, merely search for the conditions of man's becoming
and for the laws that will cause his death again. For him, birth and
death become events that draw his imagination to a life before birth
and to a life after death. Fechner writes in his Booklet on Life
after Death:
Man lives on earth not once, but three times. His first stage of life
is a continuous sleep; the second, an alternation between sleeping and
waking; the third, an eternal waking. In the first stage, man lives in
solitude and in the dark; in the second, he lives in fellowship and as
a separate being side by side and among others in a light that
reflects the surface for him; in the third stage, his life interweaves
with that of other spirits to a higher life in the highest spirit, and
his sight penetrates the essence of the finite things. In the first
phase, the body develops from its germ and produces the organs for the
second; in the second phase, the spirit develops from its germ and
produces its organ for the third; and in the third phase, the divine
germ that lies in the spirit of every human being develops. It can be
dimly felt and instinctively apprehended by a genius pointing toward a
realm beyond, which is dark for us but bright as day for the spirit of
the third phase. The transition from the first phase of life to the
second is called birth; the transition from the second to the third is
called death.
Lotze has given an interpretation of the phenomena of the world that
is in keeping with the needs of his inner disposition in his works,
Microcosm (1858 64), Three Books of Logic (1874) and
Three Books of Metaphysics (1879). The notes taken from the
lectures he gave on the various fields of philosophy also have
appeared in print. He proceeds by following the strictly natural,
law-determined course of the world and by interpreting this regularity
in the sense of an ideal, harmonious, soul-filled order and activity
of the world-ground. We see that one thing has an effect on another,
but one could not produce the effect on the other if fundamental
kinship and unity did not exist between them. The second thing would
have to remain indifferent to the activity of the first if it did not
possess the ability to behave in agreement with the action of the
first and to arrange its own activity accordingly. A ball can be
caused to move by another ball that hits it only if it meets the other
ball with a certain understanding, so to speak, if it finds within
itself the same understanding of motion as is contained in the first.
The ability to move is something that is contained in the first ball
as well as in the second, as common to both of them. All things and
processes must have such common elements. That we perceive them as
things and events is caused by the fact that we, in our observation,
become acquainted only with their surface. If we were able to see
their inner nature, we would observe not what separates them but what
connects them to form a great world totality. There is only one being
in our experience that we do not merely know from without but from
within, that we cannot merely look at, but into, that
our sight can penetrate. This is our own soul, the totality of our own
spiritual personality. But since all things must possess a common
element in their inner being, so they must also have in common with
our soul the element that constitutes our soul's inner core. We may,
therefore, conceive the inner nature of things as similar to the
quality of our own soul. The world ground that rules as the common
element of all things can be thought by us in no other way than as a
comprehensible personality after the image of our own personality.
Our heart's ardent desire to grasp the highest that it may divine can
be satisfied by no other form of existence than that of the
personality, no other form can be seriously considered. This
aspiration of our heart is so much guided by the conviction that the
living, self-possessed and self-enjoying form of the ego is the
undeniable prerequisite and the only home of all good and all values.
It is so much filled with a silent disdain of all existence that
appears lifeless, that we always find the early phases of religion,
when it is given to myth making, occupied with the attempt to
transfigure the natural reality into a spiritual one. It has, however,
never felt a need to reduce something that is spiritually alive to a
blind reality as its firmer ground.
Lotze expresses his own feeling with regard to the things of nature as
follows:
I do not know them, these dead masses of which you speak; for me
everything is life and inner alertness; rest and death are nothing but
a dull transitory appearance of an ever active inner weaving.
If natural processes, as they appear in the observation, are only such
dull transitory shadows, then one cannot expect to find their deepest
essence in the regularity that presents itself to the observation, but
in the ever active weaving of all inspiring, all
comprehensive personality, its aims and purposes. Lotze, therefore,
imagines that in all natural activity a personality's moral purpose is
manifested toward which the world is striving. The laws of nature are
the external manifestation of an all pervading ethical order of the
world. This ethical interpretation of the world is in perfect harmony
with what Lotze says concerning the continuous life of the soul after
death:
We have no other thought at our disposal than the general idealistic
conviction that every created thing or being will remain in existence
whose continuation is essential for the meaning of the world.
Everything that serves only in a transitory phase of the course of the
world will at some time cease to exist. That this principle does not
justify certain rash applications need scarcely be mentioned. We
certainly do not know the merits that would be adequate to earn the
claim for eternal existence for one being, nor the defects that would
deny it to others. (Three Books of Metaphysics)
At the point where Lotze's reflections touch the realm of the great
enigmatic problems of philosophy, his thoughts show an uncertain and
wavering character. One can notice that he does not succeed in
securing from his two sources of knowledge, natural science and
psychological self-observation, a reliable conception concerning man's
relation to the course of the world. The inner force of
self-observation does not penetrate to a thinking that could justify
the ego feeling itself as a definite entity within the totality of the
world. In his lectures, Philosophy of Religion, we read:
The belief in immortality has no other sure foundation than the
need for religion. For this reason it also impossible to state
anything beyond a simple metaphysical statement concerning the nature
of continued existence. Such a statement would be: As we regard every
entity to be merely a creature of God, there is no
fundamentally valid right that the individual soul could claim,
for instance, as a substance, to demand eternal individual
existence. We can merely maintain that every entity is preserved by
God only as long as its existence has a valuable significance for the
totality of His world plan . . .
The indefinite character of such principles expresses the extent to
which Lotze's ideas can penetrate into the realm of the great
philosophical problems.
In his little book, Life after Death, Fechner says of the
relation of man to the world:
What does the anatomist see when he looks into man's brain? A tangle
of white fibres, the meaning of which he cannot fathom. What does he
see in himself? A world of lights, sounds, thoughts, reminiscences,
fantasies, sentiments of love and hatred. In this way you must imagine
the relationship of the side of the world that you see as you are
externally confronted with it, to what this world sees in itself, and
you must not demand that the inside and the outside of the world
should show a greater similarity than in yourself, who is only a part
of it. It is only the fact that you are a part of this world that
allows you to see within yourself a part of what the world experiences
inwardly.
Fechner imagines that the world spirit stands in the same relation to
the world of matter as the human spirit does to the human body. He
then argues: Man speaks of himself when he speaks of his body, but he
also speaks of himself when he deals with his spirit. The anatomist
who investigates the tangle of dead brain fibres is confronted with
the organ that once was the source of thoughts and imaginations. When
the man, whose brain the anatomist observes, was still alive, he did
not have before him in his mind the fibres of his brain and their
physical function, but a world of mental contents. What has changed
then when, instead of a man who experiences his inner soul content,
the anatomist looks at the brain, the physical organ of that soul? Is
it not in both cases the same being, the same man that is inspected?
Fechner is of the opinion that the object is the same, merely the
point of view of the observer has changed. The anatomist observes from
outside what was previously viewed by man from inside. It is as if one
looks at a circle first from without and then from within. In the
first case, it appears convex, in the second, concave. In both cases,
it is the same circle. So it is also with man. If he looks at himself
from within, he is spirit; if the natural scientist looks at him from
without, he is body, matter.
According to Fechner's mode of conception, it is of no use to ponder
on how body and spirit effect each other, for they are not two
entities at all; they are both one and the same thing. They appear to
us only as different when we observe them from different viewpoints.
Fechner considers man to be a body that is spirit at the same time.
From this point of view it becomes possible for Fechner to imagine all
nature as spiritual, as animated. With regard to his own being, man is
in the position to inspect the physical from within and thus to
recognize the inside directly as spiritual. Does not the thought then
suggest itself that everything physical, if it could be inspected from
within, would appear as spiritual? We can see the plant only from
without, but is it not possible that it, too, if seen from within,
would prove to be a soul? This notion grew in Fechner's imagination
into the conviction that everything physical is spiritual at the same
time. The smallest material particle is animated, and the combination
of particles to form more perfect material bodies is merely a process
viewed from the outside. There is a corresponding inner process that
would, if one could observe it, present itself as the combination of
individual souls into more comprehensive souls. If somebody had the
ability to observe from within the physical processes of our earth
with the plants, animals and men living on it, the totality would
appear to him as the soul of the earth. So it would also be with the
solar system, and even with the whole world. The universe seen from
without is the physical cosmos; seen from within, it is the
all-embracing spirit, the most perfect personality, God.
A thinker who wants to arrive at a world conception must go beyond the
facts that present themselves to him without his own activity. But
what is achieved by this going beyond the results of direct
observation is a question about which there are the most divergent
views. Kirchhoff expressed his view (compare above,
to Part II Chapter III)
by saying that even through the strictest science one cannot obtain
anything but a complete and simple description of the actual events.
Fechner proceeds from an opposite viewpoint. It is his opinion that
this is the great art, to draw conclusions from this world to
the next, not from reasons that we do not know nor from
presuppositions that we accept, but from facts with which we are
acquainted, to the greater and higher facts of the world beyond, and
thereby to fortify and support from below the belief that depends on
higher viewpoints and to establish for it a living relationship toward
life. (The Booklet on Life after Death) According to this
opinion, Fechner does not merely look for the connection of the
outwardly observed physical phenomena with the inwardly experienced
spiritual processes, but he adds to the observed soul phenomena
others, the earth spirit, the planetary spirit, the world spirit.
Fechner does not allow his knowledge of natural science, which is
based on a firm foundation, to keep him from raising his thoughts from
the world of the senses into regions where they envisage world
entities and world processes, which, if they exist, must be beyond the
reach of sense perception. He feels stimulated to such an elevation
through his intimate contemplation of the world of the senses, which
reveals to his thinking more than the mere sense perception would be
capable of disclosing. This additional content he feels
inclined to use in imagining extrasensory entities. In his way,
he strives thus to depict a world into which he promises to introduce
thoughts that have come to life. But such a transcendence of sensory
limits did not prevent Fechner from proceeding according to the
strictest method of natural science, even in the realm that borders
that of the soul. It was he who created the scientific methods for
this field.
Fechner's Elements of Psychophysics (1860) is the fundamental
work in this field. The fundamental law on which he based
psychophysics states that the increase of sensation caused in man
through an increase of external impressions, proceeds proportionately
slower than the intensification of the stimulating impressions. The
greater the strength of the stimulus at the outset, the less the
sensation grows. Proceeding from this thought, it is possible to
obtain a measured proportion between the external stimulus (for
instance, the strength of physical light) and the sensation (for
instance, the intensity of light sensation). The continuation of this
method established by Fechner has resulted in the elaboration of the
discipline of psychophysics as an entirely new science, concerned with
the relation of stimuli toward sensations, that is to say, of the
physical to the psychical.
Wilhelm Wundt, who continued to work in Fechner's spirit in this
field, characterizes the founder of the science of psychophysics in an
excellent description:
Probably none of his other scientific achievements show in such a
splendid way the rare combination of gifts that were at Fechner's
disposal as do his psychophysical works. To produce a work like his
Elements of Psychophysics, it was necessary to be intimately
acquainted with the principles of the exact method of mathematical
physics and at the same time to possess an inclination to probe the
most profound problems of being, a combination that was realized only
in him. For this purpose he needed the originality of thinking that
enabled him to adapt freely the inherited research methods to fit his
own needs, and the courage never to show any hesitation to proceed
along new and untrodden paths. The observations of E. H. Weber,
which were admirable for their ingenious simplicity but limited in
their scope, the isolated and often more arbitrary than deliberately
devised experimental methods and results of other physiologists
these formed the modest material out of which he built a new science.
Important insights into the interrelation between body and soul have
resulted from the experimental method suggested by Fechner. Wundt
characterizes this new science in his Lectures on the Human and
Animal Soul (1863) as follows:
I shall show in the following exposition that the experiment is the
chief instrument in psychology. It leads us from the facts of
consciousness to those processes that prepare the conscious life in
the dark background of the soul. Self-observation provides, as does
observation in general, merely the composite phenomena. It is only
through the experiment that we free the phenomenon of all accidental
circumstances to which it is bound in nature. Through the experiment
we produce the phenomenon synthetically out of the conditions we
ourselves control. Change these conditions and we thereby also change,
in a measurable way, the phenomenon itself. In this way, it is always
the experiment that leads us to the laws of nature because only in the
experiment can we observe simultaneously the causes and the results.
It is doubtless only in a borderline territory of the field of
psychology that the experiment is really fruitful, that is, in the
territory where the conscious processes lead to the backgrounds of the
soul life where they are no longer conscious but material processes.
The psychical phenomena in the proper sense of the word can, after
all, only be obtained by a purely spiritual observation. Nevertheless,
E. Kräpelin, a psychophysicist, is fully justified when he says
that the young science will always be capable of maintaining its
independent position side by side with the other branches of the
natural sciences and particularly the science of physiology
(Psychological Works, published by E. Kräpelin, Vol. I, part 1,
page 4).
When Eduard von Hartmann published his Philosophy of the
Unconscious in 1869 he did not so much have in mind a world
conception based on the results of modern natural science but rather
one that would raise to a higher level the ideas of the idealistic
systems of the first half of the nineteenth century, since these
appeared to him insufficient in many points. It was his intention to
free these ideas of their contradictions and to develop them
completely. It seemed to him that Hegel's, Schelling's and
Schopenhauer's thoughts contained potential truths that would only
have to be fully developed. Man cannot be satisfied by merely
observing facts if he intends to know things and processes of the
world. He must proceed from facts to ideas. These ideas cannot be
considered to be an element that our thinking arbitrarily adds to the
facts. There must be something in them that corresponds to the things
and events. This corresponding element cannot be the element of
conscious ideas, for these are brought about only through the material
processes of the human brain. Without a brain there is no
consciousness. We must, therefore, assume that an unconscious ideal
element in reality corresponds to the conscious ideas of the human
mind.
Hartmann, like Hegel, considers the idea as the real element in things
that is contained in them beyond the perceptible, that is to say,
beyond the accessible to sense observation. But the mere content of
the ideas would never be capable of producing a real process within
them. The idea of a ball cannot collide with the idea of another ball.
The idea of a table cannot produce an impression on the human eye. A
real process requires a real force. In order to gain a conception of
such a force, Hartmann borrows from Schopenhauer. Man finds in his
soul a force through which he imparts reality to his thought and to
his decisions. This force is the will. In the form in which it is
manifest in the human soul the will presupposes the existence of the
human organism. Through the organism it is a conscious will. If we
want to think of a force as existing in things, we can conceive of it
only as similar to the will, the only energy with which we are
immediately acquainted. We must, however, think of this will as
something without consciousness. Thus, outside man an unconscious will
rules in things that endows them with the possibility of becoming
real. The world's content of idea and will in their combination
constitutes its unconscious basis.
Although the world, without doubt, presents a logical structure
because of its content of ideas, it nevertheless owes its real
existence to a will that is entirely without logic and reason. Its
content is endowed with reason; that this content is a reality
is caused by unreason. The rule of unreason is manifested in the
existence of the pain by which all beings are tortured. Pain
out-balances pleasure in the world. This fact, which is to be
philosophically explained from the non-logical will element, Eduard
von Hartmann tries to establish by careful investigations of the
relation of pleasure and displeasure in the world. Whoever does not
indulge in illusions but observes the evils of the world objectively
cannot arrive at any other result than that there is much more
displeasure in the world than pleasure. From this, we must conclude
that non-being is preferable to being. Non-being, however, can be
attained only when the logical-reasonable idea annihilates being.
Hartmann, therefore, regards the world process as a gradual
destruction of the unreasonable will by the reasonable world of ideas.
It must be the highest moral task of man to contribute to this
conquest of the will. All cultural progress must aim at this final
conquest. Man is morally good if he participates in the progress of
culture, if he demands nothing for himself but selflessly devotes
himself to the great work of liberation from existence. He will
without doubt do that if he gains the insight that pain must always be
greater than pleasure and that happiness is for this reason
impossible. Only he who believes happiness to be possible can maintain
an egotistic desire for it. The pessimistic view of the preponderance
of pain over pleasure is the best remedy against egotism. Only in
surrendering to the world process can the individual find his
salvation. The true pessimist is led to act unegotistically.
What man does consciously, however, is merely the unconscious, raised
into consciousness. To the conscious contribution of human work
to the cultural progress, there corresponds an unconscious
general process consisting of a progressive emancipation of the
primordial substance of the world from will. The beginning of the
world must already have served this aim. The primordial substance had
to create the world in order to free itself gradually with the aid of
the idea from the power of the will.
Real existence is the incarnation of the godhead. The world process is
the history of the passion of the incarnate God and at the same time
the path for the redemption of the God crucified in the flesh.
Morality is the cooperating work for the shortening of this path of
passion and redemption. (Hartmann, Phenomenology of the Moral
Consciousness, 1879, Page 871.)
Hartmann elaborated his world conception in a series of comprehensive
works and in a great number of monographs and articles. These writings
contain intellectual treasures of extraordinary significance. This is
especially the case because Hartmann knew how to avoid being
tyrannized by his basic thoughts in the treatment of special problems
of science and life, and to maintain an unbiased attitude in the
contemplation of things. This is true to a particularly high degree in
his Phenomenology of the Moral Consciousness in which he
presents the different kinds of human doctrines of morality in logical
order. He gives in it a kind of natural history of the
various moral viewpoints, from the egotistical hunt for happiness
through many intermediate stages to the selfless surrender to the
general world process through which the divine primordial substance
frees itself from the bondage of existence.
Since Hartmann accepts the idea of purpose for his world conception,
it is understandable that the mode of thinking of natural science that
rests on Darwinism appears to him as a one-sided current of ideas. To
Hartmann the idea tends in the whole of the world process toward the
aim of non-being, and the ideal content is for him purposeful also in
every specific phase. In the evolution of the organism Hartmann sees a
purpose in self-realization. The struggle for existence with its
process of natural selection is for him merely auxiliary functions of
the purposeful rule of ideas (Philosophy of the Unconscious,
10. Ed., Vol. III, Page 403).
The thought life of the nineteenth century leads, from various sides,
to a world conception that is characterized by an uncertainty of
thought and by an inner hopelessness. Richard Wahle declares
definitely that thinking is incapable of contributing anything to the
solution of transcendent questions, or of the highest
problems, and Eduard von Hartmann sees in all cultural work nothing
but a detour toward the final attainment of the ultimate purpose
complete deliverance from existence. Against the currents of such
ideas, a beautiful statement was written in 1843 by the German
linguist, Wilhelm Wackernagel in his book, On the Instruction in
the Mother Tongue. Wackernagel says that doubt cannot supply the
basis for a world conception; he considers it rather as an
injury that offends not only the person who wants to know
something, but also the things that are to be known.
Knowledge, he says, begins with confidence.
Such confidence for the ideas that depend on the research methods of
natural science has been produced in modern times, but not for a
knowledge that derives its power of truth from the self-conscious ego.
The impulses that lie in the depths of the development of the
spiritual life require such a powerful will for the truth. Man's
searching soul feels instinctively that it can find satisfaction only
through such a power. The philosophical endeavor strives for such a
force, but it cannot find it in the thoughts that it is capable of
developing for a world conception. The achievements of the thought
life fail to satisfy the demands of the soul. The conceptions of
natural science derive their certainty from the observation of the
external world. Within one's soul one does not find the strength that
would guarantee the same certainty. One would like to have truths
concerning the spiritual world concerning the destiny of the soul and
its connection with the world that are gained in the same way as the
conceptions of natural science.
A thinker who derived his thoughts as much from the philosophical
thinking of the past as from his penetration of the mode of thinking
of natural science was Franz Brentano (1828 1912). He
demanded of philosophy that it should arrive at its results in the
same manner as natural science. Because of this imitation of the
methods of natural science, he hoped that psychology, for instance,
would not have to renounce its attempts to gain an insight into the
most important problem of soul life.
But for the hopes of a Plato and Aristotle to attain sure knowledge
concerning the continued life of our better part after the dissolution
of our body, the laws of the association of ideas, the development of
convictions and opinions and of the origin and development of pleasure
and love would be anything but a true compensation. If this new
natural scientific method of thinking would really bring about the
elimination of the problem of immortality, this would have to be
considered as significant for psychology.
This is Brentano's statement in his Psychology from the Empirical
Standpoint, (1870, page 20).
Symptomatic of the weakness of a psychology that intends to follow the
method of natural science entirely is the fact that such a serious
seeker after truth as Franz Brentano did not write a second volume of
his psychology that would really have taken up the highest problems
after the first volume that dealt only with questions that had to be
considered as anything but a compensation for these highest
questions of the soul life. The thinkers of that time lacked the
inner strength and elasticity of mind that could do real justice to
the demand of modern times. Greek thought mastered the conception of
nature and the conception of the soul life in a way that allowed both
to be combined into one total picture. Subsequently, human thought
life developed independently of and separated from nature, within the
depths of the soul life, and modern natural science supplied a picture
of nature. From this fact the necessity arose to find a conception of
the soul life within the self-conscious ego that would prove strong
enough to hold its own in conjunction with the image of nature in a
general world picture. For this purpose, it is necessary to find a
point of support within the soul itself that carried as surely as the
results of natural scientific research. Spinoza believed he had found
it by modeling his world conception after the mathematical method;
Kant relinquished the knowledge of the world of things in themselves
and attempted to gain ideas that were to supply, through their moral
weight, to be sure, not knowledge, but a certain belief.
Thus we observe in these searching philosophers a striving to anchor
the soul life in a total structure of the world. But what is still
lacking is the strength and elasticity of thought that would form the
conceptions concerning the soul life in a way to promise a solution
for the problems of the soul. Uncertainty concerning the true
significance of man's soul experiences arises everywhere. Natural
science in Haeckel's sense follows the natural processes that are
perceptible to the senses and it sees the life of the soul only as a
higher stage of such natural processes. Other thinkers find that we
have in everything the soul perceives only the effects of extra-human
processes that are both unknown and unknowable. For these thinkers,
the world becomes an illusion, although an illusion that
is caused by natural necessity through the human organization.
As long as the art of looking around corners has not been invented,
that is, to conceive without conceptions, the proud self-restrictions
of Kant, that we can know of reality only that it is, not
what it is, will have to be acknowledged as the final decision.
This is the judgment of Robert Zimmermann, a philosopher of the second
half of the nineteenth century. For such a world conception the human
soul, which cannot have any knowledge of its own nature of
what it is, sails into an ocean of conceptions
without becoming aware of its ability to find something in this vast
ocean that could open vistas into the nature of existence. Hegel had
been of the opinion that he perceived in thinking itself the inner
force of life that leads man's ego to reality. For the time that
followed, mere thinking became a lightly woven texture of
imaginations containing nothing of the nature of true being. When, in
the search for truth, an opinion ventures to put the emphasis on
thinking, the suggested thoughts have a ring of inner uncertainty, as
can be seen in this statement of Gideon Spicker: That thinking
in itself is correct, we can never know for sure, neither empirically
nor logically . . . (Lessing's Weltanschauung, 1883, page
5).
In a most persuasive form, Philipp Mainländer (1841 1876) gave
expression to this lack of confidence in existence in his
Philosophy of Redemption. Mainländer sees himself confronted by
the world picture toward which modern natural science tends so
strongly. But it is in vain that he seeks for a possibility to anchor
the self-conscious ego in a spiritual world. He cannot achieve through
this self-conscious ego what had first been realized by Goethe,
namely, to feel in the soul the resurrection of an inner living
reality that experiences itself as spiritually alive in a living
spiritual element behind a mere external nature. It is for this reason
that the world appears to Mainländer without spirit. Since he can
think of the world only as having originated from the spirit, he must
consider it as a remainder of a past spiritual life. Statements like
the following are striking:
Now we have the right to give to this being the well-known name that
always designates what no power of imagination, no flight of the
boldest fantasy, no abstract thinking however profound, no intently
devout heart, no enraptured and transported spirit ever attained:
God. But this simple oneness is of the past; it is no
longer. In a transformation of its nature, it has dispersed itself
into a world of diversity. (Compare Max Seiling's essay,
Mainländer.)
If, in the existing world, we find only reality without value or
merely the ruins of value, then the aim of the world can only be its
destruction. Man can see his task only in a contribution to this
annihilation. (Mainländer ended his life by suicide.) According to
Mainländer, God created the world only in order to free himself from
the torture of his own existence. The world is the means for the
purpose of non-being, and it is the only possible means for this
purpose. God knew that he could change from a state of super-reality
into non-being only through the development of a real world of
multiformity. (Philosophic der Erlösung)
This view, which springs from mistrust in the world, was vigorously
opposed by the poet, Robert Hamerling (1830 89) in his posthumously
published philosophical work, Atomism of Will. He rejects
logical inquiries concerning the value or worthlessness of the world
and starts from an original inner experience:
Almost all men with very few exceptions want to live at any price, no
matter whether they are happy or unhappy. The main thing is not
whether they are right in wanting this, but that they
want this; this is simply undeniable. Yet the doctrinarian pessimists
do not consider this decisive fact. They only balance, in learned
reflections, pleasure and pain as life brings them in its particular
instances. Since pleasure and pain are matters of feeling, it is
feeling and not intellect that is decisive in striking the balance of
pleasure and pain. This balance is actually to be found in all
humanity, one can even say in everything that has life, and is in
favor of the pleasure of existence. That everything alive wants to
live and wants this under all circumstances, wants to live at any
price, is the great fact against which all doctrinarian talk is
powerless.
Hamerling then contemplates the thought: There is something in the
depth of the soul that clings to existence, expressing the nature of
the soul with more truth than the judgments that are encumbered by the
mode of conception of modern natural science as they speak of the
value of life. One could say that Hamerling feels a spiritual point of
gravity in the depth of the soul that anchors the self-conscious ego
in the living and moving world. He is, therefore, inclined to see in
this ego something that guarantees its existence more than the thought
structures of the philosophers. He finds a main defect in modern world
conception in the opinion that there is too much sophistry in
the most recent philosophy directed against the ego, and he
would like to explain this from the fear of the soul, of
a special soul-entity or even a thing-like conception of a soul.
Hamerling points significantly to the really important question,
The ideas of the ego are interwoven with the elements of
feeling. . . . What the spirit has not experienced, it is also
incapable of thinking. . . . For Hamerling, all higher world
conception hinges on the necessity of feeling the act of thinking
itself, of experiencing it inwardly. The possibility of penetrating
into those soul-depths in which the living conceptions can be attained
that lead to a knowledge of the soul entity through the inner strength
of the self-conscious ego is, according to Hamerling, barred by a
layer of concepts that originated in the course of the development of
modern world conception, and change the world picture into a mere
ocean of ideas. He introduces his philosophy, therefore, with the
following words:
Certain stimuli produce odors within our organ of smell. Thus, the
rose has no fragrance if nobody smells it. Certain air vibrations
produce sounds in the ear. Sound then does not exist without an ear. A
gunshot would not ring out if nobody heard it.
Such conceptions have in the course of modern thought development
become so definite a part of thinking that Hamerling added to the
quoted exposition the words:
If this, dear reader, does not seem plausible to you, if your mind
stirs like a shy horse when it is confronted with this fact, do not
bother to read another line; leave this book and all others that deal
with philosophical things unread, for you lack the ability that is
necessary for this purpose, that is, to apprehend a fact without bias
and to adhere to it in your thoughts. (Atomism of Will)
Hamerling's last poetic effort was his Homunculus. In this work
he intended to present a criticism of modern civilization. He
portrayed in a radical way in a series of pictures what a humanity is
drifting to that has become soulless and believes only in the power of
external natural laws. As the poet of Homunculus, he knows no
limit to his criticism of everything in this civilization that is
caused by this false belief. As a thinker, however, Hamerling
nevertheless capitulates in the full sense of the word to the mode of
conception described in this book in the chapter, The World as
Illusion. He does not hesitate to use words like the following.
The extended spatial corporeal world as such exists only insofar as we
perceive it. Anyone who adheres to this principle will understand what
a naive error it is to believe that there is, in addition to the
impression (Vorstellung) that we call horse
still another horse, which is actually the real horse and of which
our inner impression is only a kind of copy. Outside of myself, let it
be said again, there is only the sum total of those conditions that
produce within my senses an idea (Anschauung) that I call
horse.
With respect to the soul life, Hamerling feels as if nothing of the
world's own nature could ever penetrate into the ocean of its thought
pictures. But he has a feeling for the process that goes on in the
depths of modern soul development. He feels that the knowledge of
modern man must vigorously light up with its own power of truth within
the self-conscious ego, as it had manifested itself in the perceived
thought of the Greeks. Again and again he probes his way toward the
point where the self-conscious ego feels itself endowed with the
strength of its true being that is at the same time aware of standing
within the spiritual life of the world. But he only senses this and
thus fails to arrive at any further revelation. So he clings to the
feeling of existence that pulsates within his soul and that seems to
him more substantial, more saturated with reality than the mere
conceptions of the ego, the mere thought of the ego. From the
awareness or feeling of our own being we gain a concept of
being that goes far beyond the status of being merely an object of
thought. We gain the concept of a being that not merely is
thought, but thinks.
Starting from this ego that apprehends itself in its feeling of
existence, Hamerling attempts to gain a world picture. What the ego
experiences in its feeling of existence is, according to him,
the atom-feeling within us (Atomgefühl). The ego
knows of itself, and it knows itself as an atom in
comparison with the world. It must imagine other beings as it finds
itself in itself: as atoms that experience and feel themselves. For
Hamerling, this seems to be synonymous with atoms of will, with
will-endowed monads. For Hamerling's Atomism of Will,
the world becomes a multitude of will-endowed monads, and the
human soul is one of the will-monads. The thinker of such a world
picture looks around himself and sees the world as spiritual, to be
sure, but all he can discover of the spirit is a manifestation of the
will. He can say nothing more about it. This world picture reveals
nothing that would answer the questions concerning the human soul's
position in the evolutionary process of the world, for whether one
considers the soul as what it appears before all philosophical
thinking, or whether one characterizes it according to this thinking
as a monad of will, it is necessary to raise the same enigmatic
questions with regard to both soul-conceptions. If one thought like
Brentano, one could say, For the hopes of a Plato and
Aristotle to attain sure knowledge concerning the continued life of
our better part after the dissolution of our body, the knowledge that
the soul is a monad of will among other monads of will is anything but
a true compensation.
In many currents of modern philosophical life one notices the
instinctive tendency (living in the subconsciousness of the thinkers)
to find in the self-conscious ego a force that is unlike that of
Spinoza, Kant, Leibniz and others. One seeks a force through
which this ego, the core of the human soul can be so conceived that
man's position in the course and the evolution of the world can become
revealed. At the same time, these philosophical currents show that the
means used in order to find such a force have not enough intensity in
order to fulfill the hopes of a Plato and Aristotle (in
Brentano's sense) to do justice to the modern demands of the soul. One
succeeds in developing opinions, for instance, concerning the possible
relation of our perceptions to the things outside, or concerning the
development and association of ideas, of the genesis of memory, and of
the relation of feeling and will to imagination and perception. But
through one's own mode of conception one locks the doors to questions
that are concerned with the hopes of Plato and Aristotle.
It is believed that through everything that could be thought with
regard to these hopes, the demands of a strictly
scientific procedure would be offended that have been set as standards
by the mode of thinking of natural science.
The ideas of the philosophical thought picture of Wilhelm Wundt (1832
1920) aim no higher than their natural scientific basis permits. For
Wundt, philosophy is the general knowledge that has been
produced by the special sciences Wundt, System of
Philosophy). By the methods of such a philosophy it is only
possible to continue the lines of thought created by the special
sciences, to combine them, and to put them into a clearly arranged
order. This Wundt does, and thus he allows the general form of his
ideas to become entirely dependent on the habits of conception that
develop in a thinker who, like Wundt, is acquainted with the special
sciences, that is, a person who has been active in some particular
field of knowledge such as the psychophysical aspect of psychology.
Wundt looks at the world picture that the human soul produces through
sense experience and at the conceptions that are experienced in the
soul under the influence of this world picture. The scientific method
considers sense perceptions as effects of processes outside man. For
Wundt, this mode of conception is, in a certain sense, an unquestioned
matter of course. He considers as external reality, therefore, what is
inferred conceptually on the basis of sense perceptions. This external
reality as such is not inwardly experienced; it is assumed by the soul
in the same way that a process is assumed to exist outside man that
effects the eye, causing, through its activity, the sensation of
light. Contrary to this process, the processes in the soul are
immediately experienced. Here our knowledge is in no need of
conclusions but needs only observations concerning the
formation and connection of our ideas and their relation to our
feelings and will impulses. In these observations we deal only with
soul activities that are apparent in the stream of consciousness, and
we have no right to speak of a special soul that is manifested in this
stream of consciousness. To assume matter to be the basis of the
natural phenomena is justifiable for, from sense perceptions, one must
conclude, by means of concepts, that there are material processes. It
is not possible in the same sense to infer a soul from the psychic
processes.
The auxiliary concept of matter is . . . bound to the indirect or
conceptual nature of all natural science. It is impossible to conceive
how the direct and intuitive inner experience should demand such an
auxiliary concept as well. . . . (Wundt, System of Philosophy).
In this way, the question of the nature of the soul is, for Wundt, a
problem to which in the last analysis neither the observation of the
inner experience nor any conclusions from these experiences can lead.
Wundt does not observe a soul; he perceives only psychical activity.
This psychical activity is so manifested that whenever it appears, a
parallel physical process takes place at the same time. Both
phenomena, the psychical activity and the physical process, are parts
of one reality: they are in the last analysis the same thing; only man
separates them in his observation. Wundt is of the opinion that a
scientific experience can recognize only such spiritual processes as
are bound to physical processes. For him, the self-conscious ego
dissolves into the psychical organism of the spiritual processes that
are to him identical with the physical processes, except that these
appear as spiritual-psychical when they are seen from within.
But if the ego tries to find what it can consider as characteristic
for its own nature, it discovers its will-activity. Only by its
will does it distinguish itself as a self-dependent entity from
the rest of the world. The ego thus sees itself induced to acknowledge
in will the fundamental character of being. Considering its own
nature, the ego admits that it may assume will-activity as the source
of the world. The inner nature of the things that man observes
in the external world remains concealed behind the observation. In his
own being he recognizes the will as the essence and may conclude that
what meets his will from the external world is of a nature homogeneous
with his will. As the will activities of the world meet and affect one
another, they produce in one another the ideas, the inner life of the
units of will. This all goes to show how Wundt is driven by the
fundamental impulse of the self-conscious ego. He goes down into man's
own entity until he meets the ego that manifests itself as will and,
taking his stand within the will-entity of the ego, he feels justified
to attribute to the entire world the same entity that the soul
experiences within itself. In this world of will, also, nothing
answers the hopes of Plato and Aristotle.
Hamerling approaches the riddles of the world and of the soul as a man
of the nineteenth century whose disposition of mind is enlivened by
the spiritual impulses that are at work in his time. He feels these
spiritual impulses in his free and deeply human being to which it is
only natural to ask questions concerning the riddle of human
existence, just as it is natural for ordinary man to feel hunger and
thirst. Concerning his relation to philosophy, he says:
I felt myself above all as a human being, as a whole and full human
being, and it was thus that the great problems of existence and life
were my most intimate spiritual interest. I did not turn suddenly
toward philosophy. It was not that I accidentally developed an
inclination in that direction, nor because I wanted to try myself out
in a new field. I have been occupied with the great problems of human
knowledge from my early youth through the natural and irresistible
bent that drives man in general to the inquiry of the truth and to the
solution of the riddles of existence. Nor could I ever regard
philosophy as a special science, which one could take up or neglect as
one would statistics or forestry. But I always considered it to be the
investigation of questions of the most intimate, the most important
and the most interesting human concern. (Atomism of Will)
In the course that his philosophical investigations take, Hamerling
becomes affected by forces of thought that had, in Kant, deprived
knowledge of the power to penetrate to the root of existence and that
led during the nineteenth century to the opinion that the world was an
illusion of our mind. Hamerling did not surrender unconditionally to
this influence but it does encumber his view. He searched within the
self-conscious ego for a point of gravity in which reality was to be
experienced and he believed he had found this point in the will.
Thinking was not felt by Hamerling as it had been experienced in
Hegel. Hamerling saw it only as mere thinking that is
powerless to seize upon reality. In this way, Hamerling appraised the
will in which he believed he experienced the force of being.
Strengthened by the will apprehended in the ego as a real force, he
meant to plunge into a world of will-monads.
Hamerling starts from an experience of the world riddles, which he
feels as vividly and as directly as a hunger of the soul. Wundt
is driven to these questions by the results to be found in the broad
field of the special sciences of modern times. In the manner in which
he raises his questions on the basis of these sciences, we feel the
specific power and the intellectual disposition of these sciences. His
answers to these problems are, as in Hamerling, much influenced by the
directing forces of modern thought that deprive this form of thinking
of the possibility to feel itself within the wellspring of reality. It
is for this reason that Wundt's world picture becomes a mere
ideal survey of the nature picture of the modern mode of
conception. For Wundt also, it is only the will in the human
soul that proves to be the element that cannot be entirely deprived of
all being through the impotence of thinking. The will so obtrudes
itself into the world conception that it seems to reveal its
omnipotence in the whole circumference of existence.
In Hamerling and Wundt two personalities emerge in the course of the
development of philosophy who are motivated by forces that attempt to
master by thought the world riddles with which the human soul finds
itself confronted through its own experience as well as through the
results of science. But in both personalities these forces have the
effect of finding within themselves nothing that would allow the
self-conscious ego to feel itself within the source of reality. These
forces rather reach a point where they can no longer uphold the
contact with the great riddles of the universe. What they cling to is
the will, but from this world of will nothing can be learned that
would assure us of the continued life of our better part after
the dissolution of the body, or that would even touch on the
riddles of the soul and the world. Such world conceptions originate
from the natural irrepressible bent that drives man in general
to the investigation of the truth and to the solution of the riddles
of existence. Since they use the means that, according to the
opinion of certain temporary tendencies, appear as the only
justifiable ones, they arrive at a mode of conception that contains no
elements of experience to bring about the solution.
It is apparent that man sees himself at a given time confronted with
the problems of the world in a definite form; he feels instinctively
what he has to do. It is his responsibility to find the means for the
answer. In using these means he may not be equal to the challenge
presenting itself from the depths of the spiritual evolution.
Philosophies that work under such conditions represent a struggle
for an aim of which they are not quite consciously aware. The aim
of the evolution of the modern world conception is to experience
something within the self-conscious ego that gives being and reality
to the ideas of the world picture. The characterized philosophical
trends prove powerless to attain such life and such reality. Thought
no longer gives to the ego or the self-conscious soul, the inner
support that insures existence. This ego has moved too far away from
the ground of nature to believe in such a guarantee as was once
possible in ancient Greece. It has not as yet brought to life within
itself what this ground of nature once supplied without demanding a
spontaneous creativity of the soul.
|
Last Modified: 17-Jul-2009 |
The Rudolf Steiner Archive is maintained by:
The e.Librarian:
elibrarian@elib.com
|
|
|
|
|