Search over 40,000 articles from the original, classic Encyclopedia Britannica, 11th Edition.
See also:JOUFFROY, See also:THEODORE See also:SIMON (1796-1842) , See also:French philosopher, was See also:born at Pontets, near Mouthe, See also:department of See also:Doubs. In his tenth See also:year, his See also:father, a tax-gatherer, sent him to an See also:uncle at See also:Pontarlier, under whom he commenced his classical studies. At See also:Dijon his compositions attracted the See also:attention of an inspector, who had him placed (1814) in the normal school, See also:Paris. He there came under the See also:influence of See also:Victor See also:Cousin, and in 1817 he was appointed assistant See also:professor of See also:philosophy at the normal and See also:Bourbon See also:schools. Three years later, being thrown upon his own resources, he began a course of lectures in his own See also:house, and formed See also:literary connexions with Le Courrier See also:francais, Le Globe, L'Encyclopedie moderne, and La Revue europeenne. The variety of his pursuits at this See also:time carried him over the whole See also: In 1833 he was appointed professor of See also:Greek and See also:Roman philosophy at the See also:college of See also:France and a member of the See also:Academy of Sciences; he then published the Melanges philosophiques (4th ed. 1866; Eng. trans. G. See also:Ripley, See also:Boston, 1835 and 1838), a collection of fugitive papers in criticism and philosophy and See also:history. In them is foreshadowed all that he afterwards worked out in See also:metaphysics, See also:psychology, See also:ethics and See also:aesthetics. He had already demonstrated in his prefaces the possibility of a psychology apart from See also:physiology, of the See also:science of the phenomena of consciousness distinct from the perceptions of sense. He now classified the See also:mental faculties, premising that they must not be confounded with capacities or properties of mind. They were, according to his See also:analysis, See also:personal will, See also:primitive instincts, voluntary movement, natural and artificial signs, sensibility and the faculties of See also:intellect ; on this analytic he founded his See also:scheme of the universe. In 1835 he published a Cours de See also:droit naturel (4th ed. 1866), which, for precision of statement and logical coherence, is the most important of his works. From the conception of a universal See also:order in the universe he reasons to a Supreme Being, who has created it and who has conferred upon every See also:man in See also:harmony with it the aim of his existence, leading to his highest See also:good. Good, he says, is the fulfilment of man's destiny, evil the thwarting of it. Every man being organized in a particular way has, of See also:necessity, an aim, the fulfilment of which is good; and he has faculties for accomplishing it, directed by See also:reason. The aim is good, however, only when reason guides it for the benefit of the See also:majority, but that is not See also:absolute good. When reason rises to the conception of universal order, when actions are submitted, by the exercise of a sympathy working necessarily and intuitively to the See also:idea of the universal order, the good has been reached, the true good, good in itself, absolute good. But he does not follow his idea into the details of human See also:duty, though he passes in See also:review See also:fatalism, See also:mysticism, See also:pantheism, scepticism, egotism, sentimentalism and See also:rationalism. In 1835 Jouffroy's health failed and he went to See also:Italy, where he continued to translate the Scottish philosophers. On his return he became librarian to the university, and took the See also:chair of See also:recent philosophy at the See also:faculty of letters. He died in Paris on the 4th of See also:February 1842. After his See also:death were published Nouveaux melanges philosophiques (3rd ed. 1872) and Cours d'esthetique (3rd ed. 1875). The former contributed nothing new to the system except a more emphatic statement of the distinction between psychology and physiology. The latter formulated his theory of beauty. Jouffroy's claim to distinction rests upon his ability as an expositor of other men's ideas. He founded no system; he contributed nothing of importance to philosophical science; he initiated nothing which has survived him. But his See also:enthusiasm for mental science, and his command over the See also:language of popular exposition, made him a See also:great See also:international See also:medium for the transfusion of ideas. He stood between See also:Scotland and France and See also:Germany and France; and, though his expositions are vitiated by loose See also:reading of the philosophers he interpreted, he did serviceable, even memorable work. See L. See also:Levy See also:Bruhl, History of Modern Philos. in France (1899), pp. 349-357; C. J. See also:Tissot, Th. Jouffroy: sa See also:vie et ses ecrits (1876) ; J. P. See also:Damiron, Essai sur l'histoire de la philos. en France an xixe siecle (1846). Additional information and CommentsThere are no comments yet for this article.
» Add information or comments to this article.
Please link directly to this article:
Highlight the code below, right click, and select "copy." Then paste it into your website, email, or other HTML. Site content, images, and layout Copyright © 2006 - Net Industries, worldwide. |
|
[back] JOUFFROY, JEAN (c. 1412–1473) |
[next] JOUGS, JUGGS, or JOGGS (O. Fr. joug, from Lat. jugu... |