Search over 40,000 articles from the original, classic Encyclopedia Britannica, 11th Edition.
SOVEREIGNTY . The word sovereignty (Fr. souverainete) is said to be derived from the See also: medieval Latin word supremitas, i.e. suprema polestas, supreme See also:power. (See See also:Skeat's Etymological See also:Dictionary as to various forms of the word, and See also:Meyer, Lehrbuch See also:des deutschen Staatsrechts, If, as to its derivation.) Sovereignty may be viewed in three ways: there is the See also:historical explanation of its origin and growth, its See also:rude beginning in the See also:savage See also:horde, its completion in the See also:modern See also:state; there is the See also:analytical or juridical explanation; there is also what (for want of a better phrase) may be called the organic explanation of sovereignty. The following are some of the See also:chief stages in the See also:history of sovereignty: While society is in a rude state or only tribally organized there is no distinct sovereignty, no power History. which all persons habitually obey. Thus there is no sovereignty among wandering See also:groups of Australian savages: each See also:family is isolated, each horde is a loose and unstable collection. When the horde has become a tribe there may exist no definite See also:sovereign. Distinct in See also:time of See also:war, the power of the chief may be fluctuating and faint in time of See also:peace; even in time of war it may be subject to the authority of a See also:council. Tribes of the same ethnic stock may See also:form a sort of federation, permanent or temporary. " With the council of the confederacy," it has been said, " and, more generally, in the confederacy, sovereignty arises and the true See also:political tradition is evolved " (F. H. See also:Giddings, Principles of See also:Sociology, p. 285).When the See also: city and the state are conterminous the seat of sovereignty becomes defined. Such was the See also:condition of things in See also:Greece, as considered by See also:Aristotle in his Politics. He discusses the question what is the supreme power in the state (3. 10), which he defines as an aggregate of citizens (3. i.), and he recognizes that it may be lodged in one, a few, or many. In his view the distinctive See also:mark of the state is not so much sovereignty (7. 4) as self-sufficiency; a state is not a See also:mere aggregate of persons; it is a See also:union of them sufficient for the purposes of See also:life (7. 8) ; sufficiency being " to have all things and to want nothing " (7. 5. I). The See also:Roman jurists say little, and only incidentally, as to sovereignty. But in the See also:middle ages, under the See also:influence of the Roman See also:law, and with the belief in the existence of an See also:empire entitled to universal sway, an absolutist theory of sovereignty was See also:developed in the writings of the jurists' who revived the study of that law: the See also:emperor was sovereign; " quod principi placuit legis habet vigorem " (Institutes, i. 2.6). Those jurists often justified the plenitudo potestatis conceded to the emperor by the fact that he stood at the )See also: lead of Christendom. Among the theories prevalent in the middle ages was one that mankind formed a unity, with the See also:pope and the emperor at the See also:head of it: the universal See also:
According to Bodin, there is in the state unlimited one power: " Majestas est summa in cives ac subditos ]egibusque soluta potestas " (i. 8). There exists a central force from which are derived all the powers which make or give effect to See also: laws; a power which he describes sometimes as " majestas summa potestas summum imperium." This was the conception ex-pressed by See also:Bossuet, " Tout 1'etat Est en la personne du See also:prince," or in Louis XIV.'s saying, " L'etat c'est moi." One favourite theory was that sovereignty originated in a social See also:contract. It was assumed that the individual members of society, by See also:express or implied pact, agree to obey some See also:person or persons; sometimes it is described as an unqualified handing over; sometimes it is a See also:transfer subject to qualifications, and with See also:notice that in certain contingencies this will be withdrawn. Gierke, in his book Johannes Althusius and See also:die Entwickelung der naturrechilichen Staatstheorie, shows (p. 76) that the conception of a treaty or agreement as the basis of the state was in the middle ages a See also:dogma which passed almost unchallenged, and that this theory was maintained up to a See also:late See also:period. It is to be found in the writings of See also:
The best-known exponent of this theory of the source of sovereignty is Rousseau, who assumes the existence of a pacte social, the terms of which are: " Chacun de nous met en commun sa personne et toute sa puissance sous la supreme direction de la volonte generale; et nous recevons encore rhaque membre comme partie indivisible de tout" (Du Contrat social, I. c. 6). It is convenient for the jurist to assume that in every state is one determined or determinable authority in which is vested sovereignty, and from which all other authorities derive their power. The See also: assumption is not true of some states; the legal authority is divided among several persons or bodies. It is at best an unfruitful assumption; and the tendency of students of sociology is to treat discussions as to sovereignty much as modern physiologists treat discussions as to " vital force " or " vitalprinciple." See also:Comte, See also:Spencer, See also:Bagehot, See also:Durkheim and Giddings, for example, refer to it, if at all, only briefly and incidentally; they conceive society as an organism, or at all events as a growing whole, no one See also:part or force being the cause of all others, and all interacting; society is not the product of any agreement or of force alone, but of a vast variety of interests, desires and needs. Now the state or See also:government comes at a certain See also:stage of organization: small groups are See also:drawn together; powerful corporations fall into See also:line; a See also:national feeling develops; eventually the state as we know it is formed. Sovereignty is a resultant of many forces. It may not exist as to some regions of conduct; as to others it may be weak and mutable; only in certain conditions is the sovereign power supreme as to all matters of conduct. Among the different senses in which " sovereign " has been used are the following: a. " Sovereign " may mean titular sovereign--the See also:
c. The political or constitutional sovereign: the See also: body of persons in whom the actual power at any moment or ultimately resides. Sometimes this is designated " the collective sovereignty." d. Sovereignty is also used in a wider sense, as the See also:equivalent of the power, actual or potential, of the whole nation or society (Gierke, 3. 568). The distinction between real and nominal sovereignty was See also:familiar to medieval writers, who recognized a See also:double sovereignty, and distinguished between (I) the real or See also:practical sovereignty See also:resident in the See also:people, and (2) the See also:personal sovereignty of the ruler (Adolf See also:Dock, Der Souveranitatsbegriff, &c., p. 13). By many writers sovereignty is regarded as resident not in any one See also:organ, but in the Gesammt person of the community (See also:Maitland, Political Theories of the Middle Ages, xliii.). Sometimes sovereignty is defined as the organized or See also:general will of the community (Combothecra, Conception juridique de l'etat, p. 96). " Sovereignty is the organized will of an organized See also:independent community. . .. The See also: kings and parliaments who serve, as its vehicles." " Sovereignty resides in the community " (Woodrow See also:
409). Sovereignty is used in a further sense when See also: Plato and Aristotle speak of the sovereignty of the laws (Laws, 4. 715; Politics, 4. 4; 3. 15). Thus Plato remarks: " I see that the state in which the law is above the rulers, and the rulers are the inferiors of the law, has salvation." (See also Gierke, Genossenschaftsrecht, 3. 8.) Even in medieval writers, such as See also:Bracton, is found the notion that the king is subject to the laws: " Bracton knows of no sovereign in the Austinian sense, and distinctly denies to the royal authority the attribute of being incapable of legal See also:limitation " (J. N. Figgis, The Divine Right of Kings, p. 13). We find the same expressed by many See also:German jurists, i.e. the idea of a state which exists only in the law and for the law, and whose life is but by a legal See also:order regulating public and private relationship (Gierke iii., x.). Among the See also:definitions of sovereignty may be quoted these: " That which decides in questions of war and peace, and of Definitions making or dissolving alliances, and about laws and ofsove- See also:capital See also:punishment, and exiles and fines, and See also:audit relgnty. of accounts and See also:examinations of administrators after their term of See also:office " (Aristotle, Politics, 4.4. 3). " Suprematum illi tribuo qui non tantum domi subditos manu militari regit, sed et qui exercitum extra fines ducere et armis, foederibus, legationibus, ac caeteris See also: juris gentium functionibus aliquid momenti ad rerum Europae generalium summam conferre potest " (Leibnitz, Opera, 4.333). " La souverainete est See also:Celle qui sert a exprimer l'independance d'un etat aussi bien a l'interieur qua l'exterieur " (F. de See also:Martens, Traite du See also:droit See also:international, translated by A. See also:Leo, 1883, i. 378). " L'independance See also:complete qui peut se manifester a See also:deuce points de vue; l'un exterieur, l'autre interieur " (Frentz Despagnet, Droit international public, 1894, p. 8o). " Sovereignty as applied to states imports the supreme, absolute, uncontrollable power by which any state is governed " (T. M. Cooley, Constitutional Limitations, p. 1)." Social control, manifesting itself in the authoritative organization of society as the state, and acting through the See also: organs of government, is sovereignty " (Giddings, Elements of Sociology, p. 217). The sovereign is " Absolut unabhangig and nur durch sich selbst beschrankt and beschrankbar " (Zorn, Volkerrecht, p. 4. See the collection of definitions in Der Souveranitatsbegriff See also:inn Bodin, &c., by Dr Adolf Dock (1897), D. 6, and in La Conception juridique de Fetal, by Combothecra, p. 9o). Many of these definitions describe an ideal state of things rather than realities. Some of the definitions would apply to the authority of powerful religious bodies in certain periods of history, or of illegal associations, such as the See also:Mafia, which have terrorized the community. Territorial sovereignty is used in a variety of senses. Often the phrase is the equivalent of sovereignty. It may mean a state of things such as existed in the middle ages, in which ownership and sovereignty were not clearly separated: when he who was owner had sovereign rights incident thereto, or, as it was some-times phrased, when sovereignty inhered in the territory, when the king was the supreme landowner (See also:Maine, See also:Ancient Law, p.1o6; Figgis, pp. 11, 14); when all political power exhibited proprietary traits, and was incident to the ownership of land (Maitland, Township and See also:
A frequent See also: deduction from the theory of the indivisibility of sovereignty is that there cannot be double See also:allegiance; in other words, no one can be the subject of two states. This deduction is not in fact true. With the existing See also:differences in the laws ofmodern states as to See also:nationality, persons may be, and are, subjects of two or more states. In the native states in See also:India there may be said to be double allegiance. C. L. See also:Tupper, in his Our See also:Indian See also:Protectorate, refers to " the double allegiance of the subjects of native states " in India; and he explains that the native rulers are themselves subject to the Indian government. " For all purposes of our relation with powers the subjects of Indian native states must be regarded as subjects of Her See also:Majesty " (Our Indian Protectorate, 1893, p. 353). Such double allegiance is See also:apt to exist in times of transition from one sovereignty to another; for example, in the 18th century, in the See also:British possessions in India, the See also:Mogul was said to exercise a personal sovereignty. As See also:Sir See also:
22, it hardly existed otherwise than as a phantom: the actual authority to be obeyed was exercised by the See also: East India See also:Company. The natives of protected states owe not only allegiance to them, but also certain duties, See also:ill defined, to the protecting state. Another deduction from the same proposition is that any See also:corporation or private body which appears to exercise sovereign powers together with the state does so only by delegation. This theory is thus stated by See also:Burke (Works, 7. 289) with reference to the East India Company: " The East India Company itself acts under two very dissimilar sorts of power, derived from two sources very remote from each other. The first source of its power is under charters which the See also:Crown of Great See also:Britain was authorized by See also:act of See also:parliament to See also:
A third See also: pro-position, often expressed with respect to sovereignty, is that it cannot be alienated: a proposition thus stated by Rousseau: " Je dis que la souverainete, n'etant que 1'exercise de la volonte See also:genet-See also:ale, ne peut jamais s'aliener " (Du Contrat social, 2. 1; Figgis, p. 89). According to one view, sovereignty is not the distinctive See also:note of a state. Many communities usually regarded as true states do not possess it. There are sovereign and non-sovereign states; international law recognizing both. In the view of many writers sovereignty is not a necessary attribute of a state (Laband, Das Staatsrecht des deutschen Reiches, 1. 87; See also:Jellinek, Die Lehre von den Staatenverbindungen, p. 37 ; Meyer, Lehrbuch des deutschen Staatsrechtes, p. 5; See also:Ullmann, Volkerrecht, 29. See the contrary view presented by See also:Professor See also:Burgess, Political See also:Science or Constitutional Law, i. 52; Political Science Quarterly, 3.123; Georges Streit, Revue de droit international, 1900, p. 14). Any See also: division or See also:classification of states must be imperfect. The fact is that there may be an indefinite number of what Merignhac (i. 204) terms political " collectivites secondaires "; that the attributes summed up in sovereignty may be separated and divided in many ways; that there may be new forms of combinations. between states or parts of states; and that their See also:morphology is subject to no hard and fast rules. The phrase See also:half sovereign states was invented by J. J. See also:Moser to describe states possessing some of the attributes of sovereignty, Under this class are grouped very diverse communi- ties. ffatt There are states which possess some attributes Sovereign of sovereignty, but no others; states possessing States. See also:internal See also:autonomy, but not externally independent; states which are more or less under the influence of others. There are also states which have certain of the attributes of sovereignty, but are subject to servitudes or burthens imposed by treaty, usage, or force. See also:Feudalism had a phraseology to express the varieties the United States was the question whether the individual states of fiefs which existed under it; modern international law has no generally-accepted terminology for the still greater variety of states which now exist. These varieties tend to multiply, and it is difficult to reduce them all to a few types. The theory that states are equal, and possess all the attributes of sovereignty, was never true.It is still more at variance with the facts in these days when a few great states predominate, and when the contact of western states with See also: African and See also:Asiatic states or communities gives rise to relations of dependence falling See also:short of See also:conquest. The division into federations, confederations and alliances is not complete. Jellinek has suggested this classification (Die Lehre von den Sta.atenverbindungen, p. 58): (a) Unorganized associations, including—(1) See also:treaties; (2) occupation of the territory of one state and See also:administration by another, as in Bosnia and See also:Cyprus; (3) alliances; (4) protectorates, guarantees, perpetual See also:neutrality; (5) Der Staatenstaat, the feudal state, of which Jellinek gives the See also:Turkish Empire and the old See also:Holy Roman Empire as examples. (b) Organized associations, including—(r) international commissions (internationale Verwaltungsvereine, such as international postal and See also:telegraph unions, &c.); (2) the Staatenbund or See also:confederation of states; (3) real unions of states as distinguished from personal; (4) the Bundesstaat or federal state.' Most of the existing varieties may be conveniently ranged in the following classes: 1. States which have complete independence, complete autonomy, external and internal, and which are recognized in international law as sovereign states. 2. States which have complete external independence, but are more or less subject permanently to other states as to their internal affairs. Of this class there are now few examples. Perhaps, however, such states as permit, permanently or normally, of interference by others on behalf of certain classes of subjects maybe so described. The general principle is that a treaty does not detract from sovereignty. As Jellinek expresses it." Der Staatenvertrag bindet, aber er unterwirft nicht " (Gesetz and Verordnung, p. 205); or as See also: Grotius (I. ch. 3, 22, 2) expresses it, Nec regi See also:aut populo See also:jus demit summi imperii." 3. States which enjoy complete autonomy as to internal affairs, but which are more or less subject to other states as to foreign relations. Some writers would See also:place in this See also:category all states forming part of a true confederacy. It includes states which are united temporarily—cases of inorganic unity, to use Jellinek's expression. It includes also permanent alliances or organic unions. These are some examples: a. Protectorates and Suzerainties.—The status of certain states, such as See also:Bulgaria and See also:Rumania and the late See also:South African See also:Republic, were See also:peculiar. Even before the independence of the two first-named states, they undoubtedly were for many purposes sovereign. b. The unions between a See also:superior and inferior state, e.g. the relations of the various states to the old Holy Roman Empire; the relations of the See also:Ottoman See also:Porte to its See also:Christian provinces.In the middle ages the question was often mooted whether states subject to feudal superiors, or the states forming the empire, were sovereign. According to one common See also: definition they were not: a true sovereign state was universitas quae non superiorem recognoscit. Celui est ahsolument souverain qui ne rien tient apres Dieu que de 1'espee. S'il tient d'autrui it n'est plus souverain." The prevalent See also:opinion, however, was that sovereignty was compatible with rights such as were possessed by the Reich over the princes of Germany; that there might be fiefs held in full sovereignty; and that See also:vassal states, when subject only to " nude vassalage," were sovereign. That was the view of Grotius (1. I. ch. 3, 23. 2), who holds that the nexus feudalis is consistent with summum imperium. 4. States which have, by treaty or otherwise, parted with some portion of their sovereignty and formed new political See also:units: what See also:Herbert Spencer calls " See also:compound political heads," or, to use See also:Austin's expression, " composite states." The most important examples of this class consist of federal or composite states which by treaty or otherwise have surrendered certain of their powers, or which have created a new state (Staatenbund).Additional information and CommentsThere are no comments yet for this article.
» Add information or comments to this article.
Please link directly to this article:
Highlight the code below, right click, and select "copy." Then paste it into your website, email, or other HTML. Site content, images, and layout Copyright © 2006 - Net Industries, worldwide. |
|
[back] SOVEREIGN |
[next] SOWAR (Hind. and Pers. suwar, a horseman) |